Łukasiewicz–Moisil algebras (LMn algebras) were introduced in the 1940s by Grigore Moisil (initially under the name of Łukasiewicz algebras[1]) in the hope of giving algebraic semantics for the n-valued Łukasiewicz logic. However, in 1956 Alan Rose discovered that for n ≥ 5, the Łukasiewicz–Moisil algebra does not model the Łukasiewicz logic. A faithful model for the ℵ0-valued (infinitely-many-valued) Łukasiewicz–Tarski logic was provided by C. C. Chang's MV-algebra, introduced in 1958. For the axiomatically more complicated (finite) n-valued Łukasiewicz logics, suitable algebras were published in 1977 by Revaz Grigolia and called MVn-algebras.[2] MVn-algebras are a subclass of LMn-algebras, and the inclusion is strict for n ≥ 5.[3] In 1982 Roberto Cignoli published some additional constraints that added to LMn-algebras produce proper models for n-valued Łukasiewicz logic; Cignoli called his discovery proper Łukasiewicz algebras.[4]
Moisil however, published in 1964 a logic to match his algebra (in the general n ≥ 5 case), now called Moisil logic.[2] After coming in contact with Zadeh's fuzzy logic, in 1968 Moisil also introduced an infinitely-many-valued logic variant and its corresponding LMθ algebras.[5] Although the Łukasiewicz implication cannot be defined in a LMn algebra for n ≥ 5, the Heyting implication can be, i.e. LMn algebras are Heyting algebras; as a result, Moisil logics can also be developed (from a purely logical standpoint) in the framework of Brower's intuitionistic logic.[6]
Definition
editA LMn algebra is a De Morgan algebra (a notion also introduced by Moisil) with n-1 additional unary, "modal" operations: , i.e. an algebra of signature where J = { 1, 2, ... n-1 }. (Some sources denote the additional operators as to emphasize that they depend on the order n of the algebra.[7]) The additional unary operators ∇j must satisfy the following axioms for all x, y ∈ A and j, k ∈ J:[3]
- if for all j ∈ J, then x = y.
(The adjective "modal" is related to the [ultimately failed] program of Tarksi and Łukasiewicz to axiomatize modal logic using many-valued logic.)
Elementary properties
editThe duals of some of the above axioms follow as properties:[3]
Additionally: and .[3] In other words, the unary "modal" operations are lattice endomorphisms.[6]
Examples
editLM2 algebras are the Boolean algebras. The canonical Łukasiewicz algebra that Moisil had in mind were over the set with negation conjunction and disjunction and the unary "modal" operators:
If B is a Boolean algebra, then the algebra over the set B[2] ≝ {(x, y) ∈ B×B | x ≤ y} with the lattice operations defined pointwise and with ¬(x, y) ≝ (¬y, ¬x), and with the unary "modal" operators ∇2(x, y) ≝ (y, y) and ∇1(x, y) = ¬∇2¬(x, y) = (x, x) [derived by axiom 4] is a three-valued Łukasiewicz algebra.[7]
Representation
editMoisil proved that every LMn algebra can be embedded in a direct product (of copies) of the canonical algebra. As a corollary, every LMn algebra is a subdirect product of subalgebras of .[3]
The Heyting implication can be defined as:[6]
Antonio Monteiro showed that for every monadic Boolean algebra one can construct a trivalent Łukasiewicz algebra (by taking certain equivalence classes) and that any trivalent Łukasiewicz algebra is isomorphic to a Łukasiewicz algebra thus derived from a monadic Boolean algebra.[7][8] Cignoli summarizes the importance of this result as: "Since it was shown by Halmos that monadic Boolean algebras are the algebraic counterpart of classical first order monadic calculus, Monteiro considered that the representation of three-valued Łukasiewicz algebras into monadic Boolean algebras gives a proof of the consistency of Łukasiewicz three-valued logic relative to classical logic."[7]
References
edit- ^ Andrei Popescu, Łukasiewicz-Moisil Relation Algebras, Studia Logica, Vol. 81, No. 2 (Nov., 2005), pp. 167-189
- ^ a b Lavinia Corina Ciungu (2013). Non-commutative Multiple-Valued Logic Algebras. Springer. pp. vii–viii. ISBN 978-3-319-01589-7.
- ^ a b c d e Iorgulescu, A.: Connections between MVn-algebras and n-valued Łukasiewicz-Moisil algebras—I. Discrete Math. 181, 155–177 (1998) doi:10.1016/S0012-365X(97)00052-6
- ^ R. Cignoli, Proper n-Valued Łukasiewicz Algebras as S-Algebras of Łukasiewicz n-Valued Propositional Calculi, Studia Logica, 41, 1982, 3–16, doi:10.1007/BF00373490
- ^ Georgescu, G., Iourgulescu, A., Rudeanu, S.: "Grigore C. Moisil (1906–1973) and his School in Algebraic Logic." International Journal of Computers, Communications & Control 1, 81–99 (2006)
- ^ a b c Georgescu, G. (2006). "N-Valued Logics and Łukasiewicz–Moisil Algebras". Axiomathes. 16 (1–2): 123–136. doi:10.1007/s10516-005-4145-6., Theorem 3.6
- ^ a b c d Cignoli, R., "The algebras of Lukasiewicz many-valued logic - A historical overview," in S. Aguzzoli et al.(Eds.), Algebraic and Proof-theoretic Aspects of Non-classical Logics, LNAI 4460, Springer, 2007, 69-83. doi:10.1007/978-3-540-75939-3_5
- ^ Monteiro, António "Sur les algèbres de Heyting symétriques." Portugaliae Mathematica 39.1–4 (1980): 1–237. Chapter 7. pp. 204-206
Further reading
edit- Raymond Balbes; Philip Dwinger (1975). Distributive lattices. University of Missouri Press. Chapter IX. De Morgan Algebras and Lukasiewicz Algebras. ISBN 978-0-8262-0163-8.
- Boicescu, V., Filipoiu, A., Georgescu, G., Rudeanu, S.: Łukasiewicz-Moisil Algebras. North-Holland, Amsterdam (1991) ISBN 0080867898
- Iorgulescu, A.: Connections between MVn-algebras and n-valued Łukasiewicz–Moisil algebras—II. Discrete Math. 202, 113–134 (1999) doi:10.1016/S0012-365X(98)00289-1
- Iorgulescu, A.: Connections between MVn-algebras and n-valued Łukasiewicz-Moisil—III. Unpublished Manuscript
- Iorgulescu, A.: Connections between MVn-algebras and n-valued Łukasiewicz–Moisil algebras—IV. J. Univers. Comput. Sci. 6, 139–154 (2000) doi:10.3217/jucs-006-01-0139
- R. Cignoli, Algebras de Moisil de orden n, Ph.D. Thesis, Universidad National del Sur, Bahia Blanca, 1969
- http://projecteuclid.org/download/pdf_1/euclid.ndjfl/1093635424