Monotone convergence theorem

(Redirected from Beppo Levi's lemma)

In the mathematical field of real analysis, the monotone convergence theorem is any of a number of related theorems proving the good convergence behaviour of monotonic sequences, i.e. sequences that are non-increasing, or non-decreasing. In its simplest form, it says that a non-decreasing bounded-above sequence of real numbers converges to its smallest upper bound, its supremum. Likewise, a non-increasing bounded-below sequence converges to its largest lower bound, its infimum. In particular, infinite sums of non-negative numbers converge to the supremum of the partial sums if and only if the partial sums are bounded.

For sums of non-negative increasing sequences , it says that taking the sum and the supremum can be interchanged.

In more advanced mathematics the monotone convergence theorem usually refers to a fundamental result in measure theory due to Lebesgue and Beppo Levi that says that for sequences of non-negative pointwise-increasing measurable functions , taking the integral and the supremum can be interchanged with the result being finite if either one is finite.

Convergence of a monotone sequence of real numbers

edit

Every bounded-above monotonically nondecreasing sequence of real numbers is convergent in the real numbers because the supremum exists and is a real number. The proposition does not apply to rational numbers because the supremum of a sequence of rational numbers may be irrational.

Proposition

edit

(A) For a non-decreasing and bounded-above sequence of real numbers

 

the limit   exists and equals its supremum:

 

(B) For a non-increasing and bounded-below sequence of real numbers

 

the limit   exists and equals its infimum:

 .

Proof

edit

Let   be the set of values of  . By assumption,   is non-empty and bounded above by  . By the least-upper-bound property of real numbers,   exists and  . Now, for every  , there exists   such that  , since otherwise   is a strictly smaller upper bound of  , contradicting the definition of the supremum  . Then since   is non decreasing, and   is an upper bound, for every  , we have

 

Hence, by definition  .

The proof of the (B) part is analogous or follows from (A) by considering  .

Theorem

edit

If   is a monotone sequence of real numbers, i.e., if   for every   or   for every  , then this sequence has a finite limit if and only if the sequence is bounded.[1]

Proof

edit
  • "If"-direction: The proof follows directly from the proposition.
  • "Only If"-direction: By (ε, δ)-definition of limit, every sequence   with a finite limit   is necessarily bounded.

Convergence of a monotone series

edit

There is a variant of the proposition above where we allow unbounded sequences in the extended real numbers, the real numbers with   and   added.

 

In the extended real numbers every set has a supremum (resp. infimum) which of course may be   (resp.  ) if the set is unbounded. An important use of the extended reals is that any set of non negative numbers   has a well defined summation order independent sum

 

where   are the upper extended non negative real numbers. For a series of non negative numbers

 

so this sum coincides with the sum of a series if both are defined. In particular the sum of a series of non negative numbers does not depend on the order of summation.

Theorem (monotone convergence of non negative sums)

edit

Let   be a sequence of non-negative real numbers indexed by natural numbers   and  . Suppose that   for all  . Then[2]: 168 

 

Remark The suprema and the sums may be finite or infinite but the left hand side is finite if and only if the right hand side is.

proof: Since   we have   so  . Conversely, we can interchange sup and sum for finite sums so   hence  .

The theorem states that if you have an infinite matrix of non-negative real numbers   such that

  • the rows are weakly increasing and each is bounded   where the bounds are summable  

then

  • for each column, the non decreasing column sums   are bounded hence convergent, and the limit of the column sums is equal to the sum of the "limit column"   which element wise is the supremum over the row.

As an example, consider the expansion

 

Now set

 

for   and   for  , then   with   and

 .

The right hand side is a non decreasing sequence in  , therefore

 .

Beppo Levi's lemma

edit

The following result is a generalisation of the monotone convergence of non negative sums theorem above to the measure theoretic setting. It is a cornerstone of measure and integration theory with many applications and has Fatou's lemma and the dominated convergence theorem as direct consequence. It is due to Beppo Levi, who proved a slight generalization in 1906 of an earlier result by Henri Lebesgue. [3] [4]

Let   denotes the  -algebra of Borel sets on the upper extended non negative real numbers  . By definition,   contains the set   and all Borel subsets of  

Theorem (monotone convergence theorem for non-negative measurable functions)

edit

Let   be a measure space, and   a measurable set. Let   be a pointwise non-decreasing sequence of  -measurable non-negative functions, i.e. each function   is  -measurable and for every   and every  ,

 

Then the pointwise supremum

 

is a  -measurable function and

 

Remark 1. The integrals and the suprema may be finite or infinite, but the left-hand side is finite if and only if the right-hand side is.

Remark 2. Under the assumptions of the theorem,

  1.  
  2.  

Note that the second chain of equalities follows from monoticity of the integral (lemma 2 below). Thus we can also write the conclusion of the theorem as

 

with the tacit understanding that the limits are allowed to be infinite.

Remark 3. The theorem remains true if its assumptions hold  -almost everywhere. In other words, it is enough that there is a null set   such that the sequence   non-decreases for every   To see why this is true, we start with an observation that allowing the sequence   to pointwise non-decrease almost everywhere causes its pointwise limit   to be undefined on some null set  . On that null set,   may then be defined arbitrarily, e.g. as zero, or in any other way that preserves measurability. To see why this will not affect the outcome of the theorem, note that since   we have, for every  

  and  

provided that   is  -measurable.[5]: section 21.38  (These equalities follow directly from the definition of the Lebesgue integral for a non-negative function).

Remark 4. The proof below does not use any properties of the Lebesgue integral except those established here. The theorem, thus, can be used to prove other basic properties, such as linearity, pertaining to Lebesgue integration.

Proof

edit

This proof does not rely on Fatou's lemma; however, we do explain how that lemma might be used. Those not interested in this independency of the proof may skip the intermediate results below.

Intermediate results

edit

We need three basic lemmas. In the proof below, we apply the monotonic property of the Lebesgue integral to non-negative functions only. Specifically (see Remark 4),

Monotonicity of the Lebesgue integral

edit

lemma 1 . let the functions   be  -measurable.

  • If   everywhere on   then
 
  • If   and   then
 

Proof. Denote by   the set of simple  -measurable functions   such that   everywhere on  

1. Since   we have   hence

 

2. The functions   where   is the indicator function of  , are easily seen to be measurable and  . Now apply 1.

Lebesgue integral as measure
edit

Lemma 2. Let   be a measurable space. Consider a simple  -measurable non-negative function  . For a measurable subset  , define

 

Then   is a measure on  .

proof (lemma 2)

edit

Write   with   and measurable sets  . Then

 

Since finite positive linear combinations of countably additive set functions are countably additive, to prove countable additivity of   it suffices to prove that, the set function defined by   is countably additive for all  . But this follows directly from the countable additivity of  .

Continuity from below
edit

Lemma 3. Let   be a measure, and  , where

 

is a non-decreasing chain with all its sets  -measurable. Then

 

proof (lemma 3)

edit

Set  , then we decompose   as a countable disjoint union of measurable sets and likewise   as a finite disjoint union. Therefore  , and   so  .

Proof of theorem

edit

Set  . Denote by   the set of simple  -measurable functions   (  nor included!) such that   on  .

Step 1. The function   is  –measurable, and the integral   is well-defined (albeit possibly infinite)[5]: section 21.3 

From   we get  . Hence we have to show that   is  -measurable. To see this, it suffices to prove that   is  -measurable for all  , because the intervals   generate the Borel sigma algebra on the extended non negative reals   by complementing and taking countable intersections, complements and countable unions.

Now since the   is a non decreasing sequence,   if and only if   for all  . Since we already know that   and   we conclude that

 

Hence   is a measurable set, being the countable intersection of the measurable sets  .

Since   the integral is well defined (but possibly infinite) as

 .

Step 2. We have the inequality

 

This is equivalent to   for all   which follows directly from   and "monotonicity of the integral" (lemma 1).

step 3 We have the reverse inequality

 .

By the definition of integral as a supremum step 3 is equivalent to

 

for every  . It is tempting to prove   for   sufficiently large, but this does not work e.g. if   is itself simple and the  . However, we can get ourself an "epsilon of room" to manoeuvre and avoid this problem. Step 3 is also equivalent to

 

for every simple function   and every   where for the equality we used that the left hand side of the inequality is a finite sum. This we will prove.

Given   and  , define

 

We claim the sets   have the following properties:

  1.   is  -measurable.
  2.  
  3.  

Assuming the claim, by the definition of   and "monotonicity of the Lebesgue integral" (lemma 1) we have

 

Hence by "Lebesgue integral of a simple function as measure" (lemma 2), and "continuity from below" (lemma 3) we get:

 

which we set out to prove. Thus it remains to prove the claim.

Ad 1: Write  , for non-negative constants  , and measurable sets  , which we may assume are pairwise disjoint and with union  . Then for   we have   if and only if   so

 

which is measurable since the   are measurable.

Ad 2: For   we have   so  

Ad 3: Fix  . If   then  , hence  . Otherwise,   and   so   for   sufficiently large, hence  .

The proof of the monotone convergence theorem is complete.

Relaxing the monotonicity assumption

edit

Under similar hypotheses to Beppo Levi's theorem, it is possible to relax the hypothesis of monotonicity.[6] As before, let   be a measure space and  . Again,   will be a sequence of  -measurable non-negative functions  . However, we do not assume they are pointwise non-decreasing. Instead, we assume that   converges for almost every  , we define   to be the pointwise limit of  , and we assume additionally that   pointwise almost everywhere for all  . Then   is  -measurable, and   exists, and  

Proof based on Fatou's lemma

edit

The proof can also be based on Fatou's lemma instead of a direct proof as above, because Fatou's lemma can be proved independent of the monotone convergence theorem. However the monotone convergence theorem is in some ways more primitive than Fatou's lemma. It easily follows from the monotone convergence theorem and proof of Fatou's lemma is similar and arguably slightly less natural than the proof above.

As before, measurability follows from the fact that   almost everywhere. The interchange of limits and integrals is then an easy consequence of Fatou's lemma. One has   by Fatou's lemma, and then, since   (monotonicity),   Therefore  

See also

edit

Notes

edit
  1. ^ A generalisation of this theorem was given by Bibby, John (1974). "Axiomatisations of the average and a further generalisation of monotonic sequences". Glasgow Mathematical Journal. 15 (1): 63–65. doi:10.1017/S0017089500002135.
  2. ^ See for instance Yeh, J. (2006). Real Analysis: Theory of Measure and Integration. Hackensack, NJ: World Scientific. ISBN 981-256-653-8.
  3. ^ Rudin, Walter (1974). Real and Complex Analysis (TMH ed.). Mc Craw-Hill. p. 22.
  4. ^ Schappacher, Norbert; Schoof, René (1996), "Beppo Levi and the arithmetic of elliptic curves" (PDF), The Mathematical Intelligencer, 18 (1): 60, doi:10.1007/bf03024818, MR 1381581, S2CID 125072148, Zbl 0849.01036
  5. ^ a b See for instance Schechter, Erik (1997). Handbook of Analysis and Its Foundations. San Diego: Academic Press. ISBN 0-12-622760-8.
  6. ^ coudy (https://mathoverflow.net/users/6129/coudy), Do you know important theorems that remain unknown?, URL (version: 2018-06-05): https://mathoverflow.net/q/296540