Cardinality of the continuum

(Redirected from Beth one)

In set theory, the cardinality of the continuum is the cardinality or "size" of the set of real numbers , sometimes called the continuum. It is an infinite cardinal number and is denoted by (lowercase Fraktur "c") or [1]

The real numbers are more numerous than the natural numbers . Moreover, has the same number of elements as the power set of . Symbolically, if the cardinality of is denoted as , the cardinality of the continuum is

This was proven by Georg Cantor in his uncountability proof of 1874, part of his groundbreaking study of different infinities. The inequality was later stated more simply in his diagonal argument in 1891. Cantor defined cardinality in terms of bijective functions: two sets have the same cardinality if, and only if, there exists a bijective function between them.

Between any two real numbers a < b, no matter how close they are to each other, there are always infinitely many other real numbers, and Cantor showed that they are as many as those contained in the whole set of real numbers. In other words, the open interval (a,b) is equinumerous with , as well as with several other infinite sets, such as any n-dimensional Euclidean space (see space filling curve). That is,

The smallest infinite cardinal number is (aleph-null). The second smallest is (aleph-one). The continuum hypothesis, which asserts that there are no sets whose cardinality is strictly between and , means that .[2] The truth or falsity of this hypothesis is undecidable and cannot be proven within the widely used Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory with axiom of choice (ZFC).

Properties

edit

Uncountability

edit

Georg Cantor introduced the concept of cardinality to compare the sizes of infinite sets. He famously showed that the set of real numbers is uncountably infinite. That is,   is strictly greater than the cardinality of the natural numbers,  :

 

In practice, this means that there are strictly more real numbers than there are integers. Cantor proved this statement in several different ways. For more information on this topic, see Cantor's first uncountability proof and Cantor's diagonal argument.

Cardinal equalities

edit

A variation of Cantor's diagonal argument can be used to prove Cantor's theorem, which states that the cardinality of any set is strictly less than that of its power set. That is,   (and so that the power set   of the natural numbers   is uncountable).[3] In fact, the cardinality of  , by definition  , is equal to  . This can be shown by providing one-to-one mappings in both directions between subsets of a countably infinite set and real numbers, and applying the Cantor–Bernstein–Schroeder theorem according to which two sets with one-to-one mappings in both directions have the same cardinality.[4][5] In one direction, reals can be equated with Dedekind cuts, sets of rational numbers,[4] or with their binary expansions.[5] In the other direction, the binary expansions of numbers in the half-open interval  , viewed as sets of positions where the expansion is one, almost give a one-to-one mapping from subsets of a countable set (the set of positions in the expansions) to real numbers, but it fails to be one-to-one for numbers with terminating binary expansions, which can also be represented by a non-terminating expansion that ends in a repeating sequence of 1s. This can be made into a one-to-one mapping by that adds one to the non-terminating repeating-1 expansions, mapping them into  .[5] Thus, we conclude that[4][5]

 

The cardinal equality   can be demonstrated using cardinal arithmetic:

 

By using the rules of cardinal arithmetic, one can also show that

 

where n is any finite cardinal ≥ 2 and

 

where   is the cardinality of the power set of R, and  .

Alternative explanation for 𝔠 = 2א‎0

edit

Every real number has at least one infinite decimal expansion. For example,

1/2 = 0.50000...
1/3 = 0.33333...
π = 3.14159....

(This is true even in the case the expansion repeats, as in the first two examples.)

In any given case, the number of decimal places is countable since they can be put into a one-to-one correspondence with the set of natural numbers  . This makes it sensible to talk about, say, the first, the one-hundredth, or the millionth decimal place of π. Since the natural numbers have cardinality   each real number has   digits in its expansion.

Since each real number can be broken into an integer part and a decimal fraction, we get:

 

where we used the fact that

 

On the other hand, if we map   to   and consider that decimal fractions containing only 3 or 7 are only a part of the real numbers, then we get

 

and thus

 

Beth numbers

edit

The sequence of beth numbers is defined by setting   and  . So   is the second beth number, beth-one:

 

The third beth number, beth-two, is the cardinality of the power set of   (i.e. the set of all subsets of the real line):

 

The continuum hypothesis

edit

The continuum hypothesis asserts that   is also the second aleph number,  .[2] In other words, the continuum hypothesis states that there is no set   whose cardinality lies strictly between   and  

 

This statement is now known to be independent of the axioms of Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory with the axiom of choice (ZFC), as shown by Kurt Gödel and Paul Cohen.[6][7][8] That is, both the hypothesis and its negation are consistent with these axioms. In fact, for every nonzero natural number n, the equality   =   is independent of ZFC (case   being the continuum hypothesis). The same is true for most other alephs, although in some cases, equality can be ruled out by König's theorem on the grounds of cofinality (e.g.  ). In particular,   could be either   or  , where   is the first uncountable ordinal, so it could be either a successor cardinal or a limit cardinal, and either a regular cardinal or a singular cardinal.

Sets with cardinality of the continuum

edit

A great many sets studied in mathematics have cardinality equal to  . Some common examples are the following:

  • the real numbers  
  • any (nondegenerate) closed or open interval in   (such as the unit interval  )
  • the irrational numbers
  • the transcendental numbers
    The set of real algebraic numbers is countably infinite (assign to each formula its Gödel number.) So the cardinality of the real algebraic numbers is  . Furthermore, the real algebraic numbers and the real transcendental numbers are disjoint sets whose union is  . Thus, since the cardinality of   is  , the cardinality of the real transcendental numbers is  . A similar result follows for complex transcendental numbers, once we have proved that  .
  • the Cantor set
  • Euclidean space  [9]
  • the complex numbers  

    Per Cantor's proof of the cardinality of Euclidean space,[9]  . By definition, any   can be uniquely expressed as   for some  . We therefore define the bijection

     
  • the power set of the natural numbers   (the set of all subsets of the natural numbers)
  • the set of sequences of integers (i.e. all functions  , often denoted  )
  • the set of sequences of real numbers,  
  • the set of all continuous functions from   to  
  • the Euclidean topology on   (i.e. the set of all open sets in  )
  • the Borel σ-algebra on   (i.e. the set of all Borel sets in  ).

Sets with greater cardinality

edit

Sets with cardinality greater than   include:

  • the set of all subsets of   (i.e., power set  )
  • the set 2R of indicator functions defined on subsets of the reals (the set   is isomorphic to   – the indicator function chooses elements of each subset to include)
  • the set   of all functions from   to  
  • the Lebesgue σ-algebra of  , i.e., the set of all Lebesgue measurable sets in  .
  • the set of all Lebesgue-integrable functions from   to  
  • the set of all Lebesgue-measurable functions from   to  
  • the Stone–Čech compactifications of  ,  , and  
  • the set of all automorphisms of the (discrete) field of complex numbers.

These all have cardinality   (beth two)

See also

edit

References

edit
  1. ^ "Transfinite number | mathematics". Encyclopedia Britannica. Retrieved 2020-08-12.
  2. ^ a b Weisstein, Eric W. "Continuum". mathworld.wolfram.com. Retrieved 2020-08-12.
  3. ^ "Cantor theorem". Encyclopedia of Mathematics. EMS Press. 2001 [1994].
  4. ^ a b c Stillwell, John (2002). "The continuum problem". American Mathematical Monthly. 109 (3): 286–297. doi:10.1080/00029890.2002.11919865. JSTOR 2695360. MR 1903582.
  5. ^ a b c d Johnson, D. L. (1998). "Cardinal Numbers". Chapter 6: Cardinal numbers. Elements of Logic via Numbers and Sets. Springer Undergraduate Mathematics Series. Springer London. pp. 113–130. doi:10.1007/978-1-4471-0603-6_6. ISBN 9781447106036.
  6. ^ Gödel, Kurt (1940-12-31). Consistency of the Continuum Hypothesis. (AM-3). doi:10.1515/9781400881635. ISBN 9781400881635.
  7. ^ Cohen, Paul J. (December 1963). "The Independence of the Continuum Hypothesis". Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences. 50 (6): 1143–1148. Bibcode:1963PNAS...50.1143C. doi:10.1073/pnas.50.6.1143. ISSN 0027-8424. PMC 221287. PMID 16578557.
  8. ^ Cohen, Paul J. (January 1964). "The Independence of the Continuum Hypothesis, Ii". Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences. 51 (1): 105–110. Bibcode:1964PNAS...51..105C. doi:10.1073/pnas.51.1.105. ISSN 0027-8424. PMC 300611. PMID 16591132.
  9. ^ a b Was Cantor Surprised?, Fernando Q. Gouvêa, American Mathematical Monthly, March 2011.

Bibliography

edit

This article incorporates material from cardinality of the continuum on PlanetMath, which is licensed under the Creative Commons Attribution/Share-Alike License.