Borel–Cantelli lemma

(Redirected from Borel-Cantelli Lemma)

In probability theory, the Borel–Cantelli lemma is a theorem about sequences of events. In general, it is a result in measure theory. It is named after Émile Borel and Francesco Paolo Cantelli, who gave statement to the lemma in the first decades of the 20th century.[1][2] A related result, sometimes called the second Borel–Cantelli lemma, is a partial converse of the first Borel–Cantelli lemma. The lemma states that, under certain conditions, an event will have probability of either zero or one. Accordingly, it is the best-known of a class of similar theorems, known as zero-one laws. Other examples include Kolmogorov's zero–one law and the Hewitt–Savage zero–one law.

Statement of lemma for probability spaces

edit

Let E1, E2, ... be a sequence of events in some probability space. The Borel–Cantelli lemma states:[3][4]

Borel–Cantelli lemma — If the sum of the probabilities of the events {En} is finite   then the probability that infinitely many of them occur is 0, that is,  

Here, "lim sup" denotes limit supremum of the sequence of events, and each event is a set of outcomes. That is, lim sup En is the set of outcomes that occur infinitely many times within the infinite sequence of events (En). Explicitly,  The set lim sup En is sometimes denoted {En i.o.}, where "i.o." stands for "infinitely often". The theorem therefore asserts that if the sum of the probabilities of the events En is finite, then the set of all outcomes that are "repeated" infinitely many times must occur with probability zero. Note that no assumption of independence is required.

Example

edit

Suppose (Xn) is a sequence of random variables with Pr(Xn = 0) = 1/n2 for each n. The probability that Xn = 0 occurs for infinitely many n is equivalent to the probability of the intersection of infinitely many [Xn = 0] events. The intersection of infinitely many such events is a set of outcomes common to all of them. However, the sum ΣPr(Xn = 0) converges to π2/6 ≈ 1.645 < ∞, and so the Borel–Cantelli Lemma states that the set of outcomes that are common to infinitely many such events occurs with probability zero. Hence, the probability of Xn = 0 occurring for infinitely many n is 0. Almost surely (i.e., with probability 1), Xn is nonzero for all but finitely many n.

Proof

edit

Let (En) be a sequence of events in some probability space.

The sequence of events   is non-increasing:  By continuity from above,  By subadditivity,  By original assumption,   As the series   converges,   as required.[5]

General measure spaces

edit

For general measure spaces, the Borel–Cantelli lemma takes the following form:

Borel–Cantelli Lemma for measure spaces — Let μ be a (positive) measure on a set X, with σ-algebra F, and let (An) be a sequence in F. If   then  

Converse result

edit

A related result, sometimes called the second Borel–Cantelli lemma, is a partial converse of the first Borel–Cantelli lemma. The lemma states: If the events En are independent and the sum of the probabilities of the En diverges to infinity, then the probability that infinitely many of them occur is 1. That is:[4]

Second Borel–Cantelli Lemma — If   and the events   are independent, then  

The assumption of independence can be weakened to pairwise independence, but in that case the proof is more difficult.

The infinite monkey theorem follows from this second lemma.

Example

edit

The lemma can be applied to give a covering theorem in Rn. Specifically (Stein 1993, Lemma X.2.1), if Ej is a collection of Lebesgue measurable subsets of a compact set in Rn such that   then there is a sequence Fj of translates   such that   apart from a set of measure zero.

Proof

edit

Suppose that   and the events   are independent. It is sufficient to show the event that the En's did not occur for infinitely many values of n has probability 0. This is just to say that it is sufficient to show that  

Noting that:   it is enough to show:  . Since the   are independent:   The convergence test for infinite products guarantees that the product above is 0, if   diverges. This completes the proof.

Counterpart

edit

Another related result is the so-called counterpart of the Borel–Cantelli lemma. It is a counterpart of the Lemma in the sense that it gives a necessary and sufficient condition for the limsup to be 1 by replacing the independence assumption by the completely different assumption that   is monotone increasing for sufficiently large indices. This Lemma says:

Let   be such that  , and let   denote the complement of  . Then the probability of infinitely many   occur (that is, at least one   occurs) is one if and only if there exists a strictly increasing sequence of positive integers   such that  This simple result can be useful in problems such as for instance those involving hitting probabilities for stochastic process with the choice of the sequence   usually being the essence.

Kochen–Stone

edit

Let   be a sequence of events with   and   Then there is a positive probability that   occur infinitely often.

Proof

edit

Let  . Then, note that   and   Hence, we know that   We have that   Now, notice that by the Cauchy-Schwarz Inequality,   therefore,   We then have   Given  , since  , we can find   large enough so that   for any given  . Therefore,   But the left side is precisely the probability that the   occur infinitely often since   We're done now, since we've shown that  

See also

edit

References

edit
  1. ^ E. Borel, "Les probabilités dénombrables et leurs applications arithmetiques" Rend. Circ. Mat. Palermo (2) 27 (1909) pp. 247–271.
  2. ^ F.P. Cantelli, "Sulla probabilità come limite della frequenza", Atti Accad. Naz. Lincei 26:1 (1917) pp.39–45.
  3. ^ Klenke, Achim (2006). Probability Theory. Springer-Verlag. ISBN 978-1-84800-047-6.
  4. ^ a b Shiryaev, Albert N. (2016). Probability-1: Volume 1. Graduate Texts in Mathematics. Vol. 95. New York, NY: Springer New York. doi:10.1007/978-0-387-72206-1. ISBN 978-0-387-72205-4.
  5. ^ "Romik, Dan. Probability Theory Lecture Notes, Fall 2009, UC Davis" (PDF). Archived from the original (PDF) on 2010-06-14.
edit