A finite geometry is any geometric system that has only a finite number of points. The familiar Euclidean geometry is not finite, because a Euclidean line contains infinitely many points. A geometry based on the graphics displayed on a computer screen, where the pixels are considered to be the points, would be a finite geometry. While there are many systems that could be called finite geometries, attention is mostly paid to the finite projective and affine spaces because of their regularity and simplicity. Other significant types of finite geometry are finite Möbius or inversive planes and Laguerre planes, which are examples of a general type called Benz planes, and their higher-dimensional analogs such as higher finite inversive geometries.
Finite geometries may be constructed via linear algebra, starting from vector spaces over a finite field; the affine and projective planes so constructed are called Galois geometries. Finite geometries can also be defined purely axiomatically. Most common finite geometries are Galois geometries, since any finite projective space of dimension three or greater is isomorphic to a projective space over a finite field (that is, the projectivization of a vector space over a finite field). However, dimension two has affine and projective planes that are not isomorphic to Galois geometries, namely the non-Desarguesian planes. Similar results hold for other kinds of finite geometries.
Finite planes
editThe following remarks apply only to finite planes. There are two main kinds of finite plane geometry: affine and projective. In an affine plane, the normal sense of parallel lines applies. In a projective plane, by contrast, any two lines intersect at a unique point, so parallel lines do not exist. Both finite affine plane geometry and finite projective plane geometry may be described by fairly simple axioms.
Finite affine planes
editAn affine plane geometry is a nonempty set X (whose elements are called "points"), along with a nonempty collection L of subsets of X (whose elements are called "lines"), such that:
- For every two distinct points, there is exactly one line that contains both points.
- Playfair's axiom: Given a line and a point not on , there exists exactly one line containing such that
- There exists a set of four points, no three of which belong to the same line.
The last axiom ensures that the geometry is not trivial (either empty or too simple to be of interest, such as a single line with an arbitrary number of points on it), while the first two specify the nature of the geometry.
The simplest affine plane contains only four points; it is called the affine plane of order 2. (The order of an affine plane is the number of points on any line, see below.) Since no three are collinear, any pair of points determines a unique line, and so this plane contains six lines. It corresponds to a tetrahedron where non-intersecting edges are considered "parallel", or a square where not only opposite sides, but also diagonals are considered "parallel".
The affine plane of order 3 is known as the Hesse configuration.
More generally, a finite affine plane of order n has n2 points and n2 + n lines; each line contains n points, and each point is on n + 1 lines.
Finite projective planes
editA projective plane geometry is a nonempty set X (whose elements are called "points"), along with a nonempty collection L of subsets of X (whose elements are called "lines"), such that:
- For every two distinct points, there is exactly one line that contains both points.
- The intersection of any two distinct lines contains exactly one point.
- There exists a set of four points, no three of which belong to the same line.
An examination of the first two axioms shows that they are nearly identical, except that the roles of points and lines have been interchanged. This suggests the principle of duality for projective plane geometries, meaning that any true statement valid in all these geometries remains true if we exchange points for lines and lines for points. The smallest geometry satisfying all three axioms contains seven points. In this simplest of the projective planes, there are also seven lines; each point is on three lines, and each line contains three points.
This particular projective plane is sometimes called the Fano plane. If any of the lines is removed from the plane, along with the points on that line, the resulting geometry is the affine plane of order 2. The Fano plane is called the projective plane of order 2 because it is unique (up to isomorphism). In general, the projective plane of order n has n2 + n + 1 points and the same number of lines; each line contains n + 1 points, and each point is on n + 1 lines.
A permutation of the Fano plane's seven points that carries collinear points (points on the same line) to collinear points is called a collineation of the plane. The full collineation group is of order 168 and is isomorphic to the group PSL(2,7) ≈ PSL(3,2), which in this special case is also isomorphic to the general linear group GL(3,2) ≈ PGL(3,2).
Order of planes
editA finite plane of order n is one such that each line has n points (for an affine plane), or such that each line has n + 1 points (for a projective plane). One major open question in finite geometry is:
- Is the order of a finite plane always a prime power?
This is conjectured to be true.
Affine and projective planes of order n exist whenever n is a prime power (a prime number raised to a positive integer exponent), by using affine and projective planes over the finite field with n = pk elements. Planes not derived from finite fields also exist (e.g. for ), but all known examples have order a prime power.[1]
The best general result to date is the Bruck–Ryser theorem of 1949, which states:
- If n is a positive integer of the form 4k + 1 or 4k + 2 and n is not equal to the sum of two integer squares, then n does not occur as the order of a finite plane.
The smallest integer that is not a prime power and not covered by the Bruck–Ryser theorem is 10; 10 is of the form 4k + 2, but it is equal to the sum of squares 12 + 32. The non-existence of a finite plane of order 10 was proven in a computer-assisted proof that finished in 1989 – see (Lam 1991) for details.
The next smallest number to consider is 12, for which neither a positive nor a negative result has been proved.
History
editIndividual examples can be found in the work of Thomas Penyngton Kirkman (1847) and the systematic development of finite projective geometry given by von Staudt (1856).
The first axiomatic treatment of finite projective geometry was developed by the Italian mathematician Gino Fano. In his work[2] on proving the independence of the set of axioms for projective n-space that he developed,[3] he considered a finite three dimensional space with 15 points, 35 lines and 15 planes (see diagram), in which each line had only three points on it.[4]
In 1906 Oswald Veblen and W. H. Bussey described projective geometry using homogeneous coordinates with entries from the Galois field GF(q). When n + 1 coordinates are used, the n-dimensional finite geometry is denoted PG(n, q).[5] It arises in synthetic geometry and has an associated transformation group.
Finite spaces of 3 or more dimensions
editFor some important differences between finite plane geometry and the geometry of higher-dimensional finite spaces, see axiomatic projective space. For a discussion of higher-dimensional finite spaces in general, see, for instance, the works of J.W.P. Hirschfeld. The study of these higher-dimensional spaces (n ≥ 3) has many important applications in advanced mathematical theories.
Axiomatic definition
editA projective space S can be defined axiomatically as a set P (the set of points), together with a set L of subsets of P (the set of lines), satisfying these axioms :[6]
- Each two distinct points p and q are in exactly one line.
- Veblen's axiom:[7] If a, b, c, d are distinct points and the lines through ab and cd meet, then so do the lines through ac and bd.
- Any line has at least 3 points on it.
The last axiom eliminates reducible cases that can be written as a disjoint union of projective spaces together with 2-point lines joining any two points in distinct projective spaces. More abstractly, it can be defined as an incidence structure (P, L, I) consisting of a set P of points, a set L of lines, and an incidence relation I stating which points lie on which lines.
Obtaining a finite projective space requires one more axiom:
- The set of points P is a finite set.
In any finite projective space, each line contains the same number of points and the order of the space is defined as one less than this common number.
A subspace of the projective space is a subset X, such that any line containing two points of X is a subset of X (that is, completely contained in X). The full space and the empty space are always subspaces.
The geometric dimension of the space is said to be n if that is the largest number for which there is a strictly ascending chain of subspaces of this form:
Algebraic construction
editA standard algebraic construction of systems satisfies these axioms. For a division ring D construct an (n + 1)-dimensional vector space over D (vector space dimension is the number of elements in a basis). Let P be the 1-dimensional (single generator) subspaces and L the 2-dimensional (two independent generators) subspaces (closed under vector addition) of this vector space. Incidence is containment. If D is finite then it must be a finite field GF(q), since by Wedderburn's little theorem all finite division rings are fields. In this case, this construction produces a finite projective space. Furthermore, if the geometric dimension of a projective space is at least three then there is a division ring from which the space can be constructed in this manner. Consequently, all finite projective spaces of geometric dimension at least three are defined over finite fields. A finite projective space defined over such a finite field has q + 1 points on a line, so the two concepts of order coincide. Such a finite projective space is denoted by PG(n, q), where PG stands for projective geometry, n is the geometric dimension of the geometry and q is the size (order) of the finite field used to construct the geometry.
In general, the number of k-dimensional subspaces of PG(n, q) is given by the product:[8]
which is a Gaussian binomial coefficient, a q analogue of a binomial coefficient.
Classification of finite projective spaces by geometric dimension
edit- Dimension 0 (no lines): The space is a single point and is so degenerate that it is usually ignored.
- Dimension 1 (exactly one line): All points lie on the unique line, called a projective line.
- Dimension 2: There are at least 2 lines, and any two lines meet. A projective space for n = 2 is a projective plane. These are much harder to classify, as not all of them are isomorphic with a PG(d, q). The Desarguesian planes (those that are isomorphic with a PG(2, q)) satisfy Desargues's theorem and are projective planes over finite fields, but there are many non-Desarguesian planes.
- Dimension at least 3: Two non-intersecting lines exist. The Veblen–Young theorem states in the finite case that every projective space of geometric dimension n ≥ 3 is isomorphic with a PG(n, q), the n-dimensional projective space over some finite field GF(q).
The smallest projective three-space
editThe smallest 3-dimensional projective space is over the field GF(2) and is denoted by PG(3,2). It has 15 points, 35 lines, and 15 planes. Each plane contains 7 points and 7 lines. Each line contains 3 points. As geometries, these planes are isomorphic to the Fano plane.
Every point is contained in 7 lines. Every pair of distinct points are contained in exactly one line and every pair of distinct planes intersects in exactly one line.
In 1892, Gino Fano was the first to consider such a finite geometry.
Kirkman's schoolgirl problem
editPG(3,2) arises as the background for a solution of Kirkman's schoolgirl problem, which states: "Fifteen schoolgirls walk each day in five groups of three. Arrange the girls’ walk for a week so that in that time, each pair of girls walks together in a group just once." There are 35 different combinations for the girls to walk together. There are also 7 days of the week, and 3 girls in each group. Two of the seven non-isomorphic solutions to this problem can be stated in terms of structures in the Fano 3-space, PG(3,2), known as packings. A spread of a projective space is a partition of its points into disjoint lines, and a packing is a partition of the lines into disjoint spreads. In PG(3,2), a spread would be a partition of the 15 points into 5 disjoint lines (with 3 points on each line), thus corresponding to the arrangement of schoolgirls on a particular day. A packing of PG(3,2) consists of seven disjoint spreads and so corresponds to a full week of arrangements.
See also
edit- Block design – a generalization of a finite projective plane.
- Discrete space
- Finite space
- Generalized polygon
- Incidence geometry
- Linear space (geometry)
- Near polygon
- Partial geometry
- Polar space
Notes
edit- ^ Laywine, Charles F.; Mullen, Gary L. (1998-09-17). Discrete Mathematics Using Latin Squares. John Wiley & Sons. ISBN 9780471240648.
- ^ Fano, G. (1892), "Sui postulati fondamentali della geometria proiettiva", Giornale di Matematiche, 30: 106–132
- ^ Collino, Conte & Verra 2013, p. 6
- ^ Malkevitch Finite Geometries? an AMS Featured Column
- ^ Oswald Veblen (1906) Finite Projective Geometries, Transactions of the American Mathematical Society 7: 241–59
- ^ Beutelspacher & Rosenbaum 1998, pp. 6–7
- ^ also referred to as the Veblen–Young axiom and mistakenly as the axiom of Pasch (Beutelspacher & Rosenbaum 1998, pgs. 6–7). Pasch was concerned with real projective space and was attempting to introduce order, which is not a concern of the Veblen–Young axiom.
- ^ Dembowski 1968, p. 28, where the formula is given, in terms of vector space dimension, by Nk+1(n + 1, q).
References
edit- Batten, Lynn Margaret (1997), Combinatorics of Finite Geometries, Cambridge University Press, ISBN 0521590140
- Beutelspacher, Albrecht; Rosenbaum, Ute (1998), Projective geometry: from foundations to applications, Cambridge University Press, ISBN 978-0-521-48364-3, MR 1629468
- Collino, Alberto; Conte, Alberto; Verra, Alessandro (2013). "On the life and scientific work of Gino Fano". arXiv:1311.7177 [math.HO].
- Dembowski, Peter (1968), Finite geometries, Ergebnisse der Mathematik und ihrer Grenzgebiete, Band 44, Berlin, New York: Springer-Verlag, ISBN 3-540-61786-8, MR 0233275
- Eves, Howard (1963), A Survey of Geometry: Volume One, Boston: Allyn and Bacon Inc.
- Hall, Marshall (1943), "Projective planes", Transactions of the American Mathematical Society, 54 (2), American Mathematical Society: 229–277, doi:10.2307/1990331, ISSN 0002-9947, JSTOR 1990331, MR 0008892
- Lam, C. W. H. (1991), "The Search for a Finite Projective Plane of Order 10", American Mathematical Monthly, 98 (4): 305–318, doi:10.2307/2323798, JSTOR 2323798
- Malkevitch, Joe. "Finite Geometries?". Retrieved Dec 2, 2013.
- Meserve, Bruce E. (1983), Fundamental Concepts of Geometry, New York: Dover Publications
- Polster, Burkard (1999). "Yea why try her raw wet hat: A tour of the smallest projective space". The Mathematical Intelligencer. 21 (2): 38–43. doi:10.1007/BF03024845. S2CID 122352568.
- Segre, Beniamino (1960), On Galois Geometries (PDF), New York: Cambridge university Press, pp. 488–499, archived from the original (PDF) on 2015-03-30, retrieved 2015-07-02
- Shult, Ernest E. (2011), Points and Lines, Universitext, Springer, doi:10.1007/978-3-642-15627-4, ISBN 978-3-642-15626-7
- Ball, Simeon (2015), Finite Geometry and Combinatorial Applications, London Mathematical Society Student Texts, Cambridge University Press, ISBN 978-1107518438.
External links
edit- Weisstein, Eric W. "finite geometry". MathWorld.
- Incidence Geometry by Eric Moorhouse
- Algebraic Combinatorial Geometry by Terence Tao
- Essay on Finite Geometry by Michael Greenberg
- Finite geometry (Script)
- Finite Geometry Resources Archived 2011-09-27 at the Wayback Machine
- J. W. P. Hirschfeld, researcher on finite geometries
- AMS Column: Finite Geometries?
- Galois Geometry and Generalized Polygons, intensive course in 1998
- Carnahan, Scott (2007-10-27), "Small finite sets", Secret Blogging Seminar, notes on a talk by Jean-Pierre Serre on canonical geometric properties of small finite sets.
{{citation}}
: CS1 maint: postscript (link) - “Problem 31: Kirkman's schoolgirl problem” at the Wayback Machine (archived August 17, 2010)
- Projective Plane of Order 12 on MathOverflow.