Lebesgue's number lemma

(Redirected from Lebesgue number lemma)

In topology, the Lebesgue covering lemma is a useful tool in the study of compact metric spaces.

Given an open cover of a compact metric space, a Lebesgue's number of the cover is a number such that every subset of having diameter less than is contained in some member of the cover.

The existance of Lebesgue's numbers for compact metric spaces is given by the Lebesgue's covering lemma:

If the metric space is compact and an open cover of is given, then the cover admits some Lebesgue's number .

The notion of Lebesgue's numbers itself is useful in other applications as well.

Proof

edit

Direct Proof

edit

Let   be an open cover of  . Since   is compact we can extract a finite subcover  . If any one of the  's equals   then any   will serve as a Lebesgue's number. Otherwise for each  , let  , note that   is not empty, and define a function   by

 

Since   is continuous on a compact set, it attains a minimum  . The key observation is that, since every   is contained in some  , the extreme value theorem shows  . Now we can verify that this   is the desired Lebesgue's number. If   is a subset of   of diameter less than  , choose   as any point in  , then by definition of diameter,  , where   denotes the ball of radius   centered at  . Since   there must exist at least one   such that  . But this means that   and so, in particular,  .

Proof by Contradiction

edit

Suppose for contradiction that that   is sequentially compact,   is an open cover of  , and the Lebesgue number   does not exist. That is: for all  , there exists   with   such that there does not exist   with  .

This enables us to perform the following construction:

 
 
 
 
 


Note that   for all  , since  . It is therefore possible by the axiom of choice to construct a sequence   in which   for each  . Since   is sequentially compact, there exists a subsequence   (with  ) that converges to  .

Because   is an open cover, there exists some   such that  . As   is open, there exists   with  . Now we invoke the convergence of the subsequence  : there exists   such that   implies  .

Furthermore, there exists   such that  . Hence for all  , we have   implies  .

Finally, define   such that   and  . For all  , notice that:

  •  , because  .
  •  , because   entails  .

Hence   by the triangle inequality, which implies that  . This yields the desired contradiction.

References

edit
  • Munkres, James R. (1974), Topology: A first course, p. 179, ISBN 978-0-13-925495-6