An integrative level, or level of organization, is a set of phenomena emerging from pre-existing phenomena of a lower level. The levels concept is an intellectual framework for structuring reality. It arranges all entities, structures, and processes in the universe, or in a certain field of study, into a hierarchy, typically based on how complex their organization is. When arranged this way, each entity is three things at the same time: It is made up of parts from the previous level below. It is a whole in its own right. And it is a part of the whole that is on the next level above. Typical examples include life emerging from non-living substances, and consciousness emerging from nervous systems.
Levels
editThe main levels usually acknowledged are those of matter, life, mind, and society. These are called strata in philosopher Nicolai Hartmann's ontology. They can be further analyzed into more specific layers, such as those of particles, atoms, molecules, and rocks forming the material stratum, or those of cells, organisms, populations, and ecosystems forming the life stratum.
The sequence of levels is often described as one of increasing complexity, although it is not clear whether this is always true: for example, parasitism emerges on pre-existing organisms, although parasites are often simpler than their originating forms.
Philosophies
editIdeas connected to integrative levels can be found in the works of both materialist philosophers and anti-materialist ones. Some philosophers and scientists have argued against certain ideas about levels of organization (see § Arguments against levels of organization).
See also
edit- Antireductionism
- Big History
- Biological organisation
- Boundary problem (spatial analysis)
- Hierarchy theory
- Level of analysis
- Mereology
- Mereotopology
- Model of hierarchical complexity
- Modifiable areal unit problem
- Nicolai Hartmann
- Scale (analytical tool)
- Spatial scale
- Structuralism (biology)
- The central science
- Tree of knowledge system
- Unity of science
- Vitalism
References
edit- Comte, Auguste (1974) [1830–1842]. Stanislav, Andreski (ed.). The essential Comte: selected from Cours de philosophie positive. Translated by Clarke, Margaret. London: Croom Helm; New York: Barnes & Noble. ISBN 0064901815. OCLC 1032574.
- Spencer, Herbert (1877). "Super-organic evolution". The principles of sociology. A system of synthetic philosophy. Vol. 6–8. New York: D. Appleton & Company. p. 3. OCLC 2083641.
- Alexander, Samuel (1920). Space, time, and deity: the Gifford lectures at Glasgow, 1916–1918. Vol. 1916–18. London: Macmillan. OCLC 1041642.
- Sellars, Roy Wood (1922). Evolutionary naturalism. Chicago: Open Court Publishing. OCLC 172131.
- Morgan, C. Lloyd (1923). Emergent evolution. Gifford lectures. London: Williams and Norgate. OCLC 3140885.
- Conger, George P. (4 June 1925). "The doctrine of levels". The Journal of Philosophy. 22 (12): 309–321. doi:10.2307/2014178. JSTOR 2014178.
- Wheeler, William Morton (1928). Emergent evolution and the development of societies. New science series (New York, N.Y.). New York: W. W. Norton & Company. OCLC 3399922.
- Needham, Joseph (1943) [1937]. "Integrative levels: a revaluation of the idea of progress". Time: the refreshing river (essays and addresses, 1932–1942). London: G. Allen & Unwin. pp. 233–272. OCLC 1148711.
- Hartmann, Nicolai (1940). Der Aufbau der realen Welt: Grundriß der allgemeinen Kategorienlehre. Ontologie. Vol. 3. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter. doi:10.1515/9783110823844. ISBN 9783110823844. OCLC 174268798.
- Novikoff, Alex B. (March 1945). "The concept of integrative levels and biology". Science. 101 (2618): 209–215. Bibcode:1945Sci...101..209N. doi:10.1126/science.101.2618.209. JSTOR 1672950. PMID 17814095.
- Hartmann, Nicolai (1952) [1949]. New ways of ontology [Neue Wege der Ontologie]. Translated by Kuhn, Reinhard C. Chicago: H. Regnery Co. OCLC 888650.
- Feibleman, James K. (May 1954). "Theory of integrative levels". The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science. 5 (17): 59–66. doi:10.1093/bjps/V.17.59. JSTOR 685952.
- Boulding, Kenneth Ewart (April 1956). "General systems theory: the skeleton of science" (PDF). Management Science. 2 (3): 197–208. doi:10.1287/mnsc.2.3.197. JSTOR 2627132.
- Sellars, Roy Wood (September 1959). "Levels of causality: the emergence of guidance and reason in nature". Philosophy and Phenomenological Research. 20 (1): 1–17. doi:10.2307/2104949. JSTOR 2104949.
- Simon, Herbert A. (December 1962). "The architecture of complexity". Proceedings of the American Philosophical Society. 106 (6): 467–482. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.110.961. JSTOR 985254.
- Bertalanffy, Ludwig von (1968). General system theory: foundations, development, applications. New York: G. Braziller. OCLC 1465.
- Bunge, Mario (1973). "The metaphysics, epistemology and methodology of levels". Method, model, and matter. Synthese library. Dordrecht; Boston: D. Reidel. pp. 160–168. doi:10.1007/978-94-010-2519-5_9. ISBN 9027702527. OCLC 613670.
- Foskett, Douglas John (June 1978). "The theory of integrative levels and its relevance to the design of information systems". ASLIB Proceedings. 30 (6): 202–208. doi:10.1108/eb050633.
- Greenberg, Gary; Tobach, Ethel, eds. (1984). Behavioral evolution and integrative levels. The T. C. Schneirla conference series. Vol. 1. Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates. ISBN 0898593638. OCLC 10997500.
- O'Neill, Robert V.; Deangelis, Donald Lee; Waide, J. B.; Allen, Timothy F. H. (1986). A hierarchical concept of ecosystems. Monographs in population biology. Vol. 23. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. ISBN 069108436X. OCLC 13526197.
- Greenberg, Gary; Tobach, Ethel, eds. (1987). Cognition, language, and consciousness: integrative levels. The T. C. Schneirla conference series. Vol. 2. Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates. ISBN 0898597226. OCLC 15317589.
- Blitz, David (1992). Emergent evolution: qualitative novelty and the levels of reality. Episteme. Vol. 19. Dordrecht; Boston: Kluwer Academic Publishers. doi:10.1007/978-94-015-8042-7. ISBN 0792316584. OCLC 25370568.
- Pettersson, Max (1996). Complexity and evolution. Cambridge, UK; New York: Cambridge University Press. doi:10.1017/CBO9780511565564. ISBN 052145400X. OCLC 34543726. Foreword by Joseph Needham.
- Poli, Roberto (September 2001). "The basic problem of the theory of levels of reality". Axiomathes. 12 (3–4): 261–283. doi:10.1023/A:1015845217681.
- Bunge, Mario (2003). Emergence and convergence: qualitative novelty and the unity of knowledge. Toronto studies in philosophy. Toronto: University of Toronto Press. doi:10.3138/9781442674356. ISBN 0802088600. OCLC 52411064.
- DiFrisco, James (August 2017). "Time scales and levels of organization". Erkenntnis. 82 (4): 795–818. doi:10.1007/s10670-016-9844-4.
- Brooks, Daniel Stephen; Eronen, Markus I. (June 2018). "The significance of levels of organization for scientific research: a heuristic approach" (PDF). Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences. 68–69: 34–41. doi:10.1016/j.shpsc.2018.04.003. PMID 29653763.
- Brooks, Daniel Stephen; DiFrisco, James; Wimsatt, William C., eds. (2021). Levels of organization in the biological sciences. Vienna series in theoretical biology. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. doi:10.7551/mitpress/12389.001.0001. ISBN 9780262045339. OCLC 1184123324.
Arguments against levels of organization
edit- Eronen, Markus I.; Brooks, Daniel Stephen (5 February 2018). "Levels of organization in biology". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2018 ed.). See the section: "2.4 Levels skepticism and deflationary accounts".
- Eronen, Markus I. (January 2015). "Levels of organization: a deflationary account" (PDF). Biology and Philosophy. 30 (1): 39–58. doi:10.1007/s10539-014-9461-z.
- Eronen, Markus I. (3 August 2015). "Are there levels out there?". scientiasalon.wordpress.com. Retrieved 20 December 2019.
- Eronen, Markus I. (December 2013). "No levels, no problems: downward causation in neuroscience" (PDF). Philosophy of Science. 80 (5): 1042–1052. doi:10.1086/673898. JSTOR 10.1086/673898.
- Guttman, Burton S. (February 1976). "Is 'levels of organization' a useful biological concept?". BioScience. 26 (2): 112–113. doi:10.2307/1297326. JSTOR 1297326.
- Noble, Denis (February 2012). "A theory of biological relativity: no privileged level of causation". Interface Focus. 2 (1): 55–64. doi:10.1098/rsfs.2011.0067. PMC 3262309. PMID 23386960.
- Potochnik, Angela (2017). "Levels and fields of science". Idealization and the aims of science. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. pp. 161–197. doi:10.7208/chicago/9780226507194.001.0001. ISBN 9780226507057. OCLC 975478843.
- Potochnik, Angela (2021). "Our world isn't organized into levels". In Brooks, Daniel S.; DiFrisco, James; Wimsatt, William C. (eds.). Levels of organization in the biological sciences (PDF). Vienna series in theoretical biology. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. pp. 61–76. doi:10.7551/mitpress/12389.003.0007. ISBN 9780262045339. OCLC 1184123324.
- Potochnik, Angela; McGill, Brian J. (January 2012). "The limitations of hierarchical organization" (PDF). Philosophy of Science. 79 (1): 120–140. doi:10.1086/663237. JSTOR 10.1086/663237.
- Schaffer, Jonathan (September 2003). "Is there a fundamental level?" (PDF). Noûs. 37 (3): 498–517. doi:10.1111/1468-0068.00448. JSTOR 3506125.
- Thalos, Mariam (2013). Without hierarchy: the scale freedom of the universe. Oxford; New York: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199917648.001.0001. ISBN 9780199917648. OCLC 827008044.