Hall's marriage theorem

(Redirected from Marriage Theorem)

In mathematics, Hall's marriage theorem, proved by Philip Hall (1935), is a theorem with two equivalent formulations. In each case, the theorem gives a necessary and sufficient condition for an object to exist:

  • The combinatorial formulation answers whether a finite collection of sets has a transversal—that is, whether an element can be chosen from each set without repetition. Hall's condition is that for any group of sets from the collection, the total unique elements they contain is at least as large as the number of sets in the group.
  • The graph theoretic formulation answers whether a finite bipartite graph has a perfect matching—that is, a way to match each vertex from one group uniquely to an adjacent vertex from the other group. Hall's condition is that any subset of vertices from one group has a neighbourhood of equal or greater size.

Combinatorial formulation

edit

Statement

edit

Let   be a finite family of sets (note that although   is not itself allowed to be infinite, the sets in it may be so, and   may contain the same set multiple times).[1] Let   be the union of all the sets in  , the set of elements that belong to at least one of its sets. A transversal for   is a subset of   that can be obtained by choosing a distinct element from each set in  . This concept can be formalized by defining a transversal to be the image of an injective function   such that   for each  . An alternative term for transversal is system of distinct representatives.

The collection   satisfies the marriage condition when each subfamily of   contains at least as many distinct members as its number of sets. That is, for all  ,   If a transversal exists then the marriage condition must be true: the function   used to define the transversal maps   to a subset of its union, of size equal to  , so the whole union must be at least as large. Hall's theorem states that the converse is also true:

Hall's Marriage Theorem — A family   of finite sets has a transversal if and only if   satisfies the marriage condition.

Examples

edit
 
example 1, marriage condition met
Example 1
Consider the family   with   and   The transversal   could be generated by the function that maps   to  ,   to  , and   to  , or alternatively by the function that maps   to  ,   to  , and   to  . There are other transversals, such as   and  . Because this family has at least one transversal, the marriage condition is met. Every subfamily of   has equal size to the set of representatives it is mapped to, which is less than or equal to the size of the union of the subfamily.
 
example 2, marriage condition violated
Example 2
Consider   with   No valid transversal exists; the marriage condition is violated as is shown by the subfamily  . Here the number of sets in the subfamily is  , while the union of the three sets   contains only two elements.

A lower bound on the different number of transversals that a given finite family   of size   may have is obtained as follows: If each of the sets in   has cardinality  , then the number of different transversals for   is either   if  , or   if  .[2]

Recall that a transversal for a family   is an ordered sequence, so two different transversals could have exactly the same elements. For instance, the collection  ,   has   and   as distinct transversals.

Graph theoretic formulation

edit
 
blue edges represent a matching

Let   be a finite bipartite graph with bipartite sets   and   and edge set  . An  -perfect matching (also called an  -saturating matching) is a matching, a set of disjoint edges, which covers every vertex in  .

For a subset   of  , let   denote the neighborhood of   in  , the set of all vertices in   that are adjacent to at least one element of  . The marriage theorem in this formulation states that there is an  -perfect matching if and only if for every subset   of  :   In other words, every subset   of   must have sufficiently many neighbors in  .

Proof

edit

Necessity

edit

In an  -perfect matching  , every edge incident to   connects to a distinct neighbor of   in  , so the number of these matched neighbors is at least  . The number of all neighbors of   is at least as large.

Sufficiency

edit

Consider the contrapositive: if there is no  -perfect matching then Hall's condition must be violated for at least one  . Let   be a maximum matching, and let   be any unmatched vertex in  . Consider all alternating paths (paths in   that alternately use edges outside and inside  ) starting from  . Let   be the set of vertices in these paths that belong to   (including   itself) and let   be the set of vertices in these paths that belong to  . Then every vertex in   is matched by   to a vertex in  , because an alternating path to an unmatched vertex could be used to increase the size of the matching by toggling whether each of its edges belongs to   or not. Therefore, the size of   is at least the number   of these matched neighbors of  , plus one for the unmatched vertex  . That is,  . However, for every vertex  , every neighbor   of   belongs to  : an alternating path to   can be found either by removing the matched edge   from the alternating path to  , or by adding the unmatched edge   to the alternating path to  . Therefore,   and  , showing that Hall's condition is violated.

Equivalence of the combinatorial formulation and the graph-theoretic formulation

edit

A problem in the combinatorial formulation, defined by a finite family of finite sets   with union   can be translated into a bipartite graph   where each edge connects a set in   to an element of that set. An  -perfect matching in this graph defines a system of unique representatives for  . In the other direction, from any bipartite graph   one can define a finite family of sets, the family of neighborhoods of the vertices in  , such that any system of unique representatives for this family corresponds to an  -perfect matching in  . In this way, the combinatorial formulation for finite families of finite sets and the graph-theoretic formulation for finite graphs are equivalent.

The same equivalence extends to infinite families of finite sets and to certain infinite graphs. In this case, the condition that each set be finite corresponds to a condition that in the bipartite graph  , every vertex in   should have finite degree. The degrees of the vertices in   are not constrained.

Topological proof

edit

Hall's theorem can be proved (non-constructively) based on Sperner's lemma.[3]: Thm.4.1, 4.2 

Applications

edit

The theorem has many applications. For example, for a standard deck of cards, dealt into 13 piles of 4 cards each, the marriage theorem implies that it is possible to select one card from each pile so that the selected cards contain exactly one card of each rank (Ace, 2, 3, ..., Queen, King). This can be done by constructing a bipartite graph with one partition containing the 13 piles and the other partition containing the 13 ranks. The remaining proof follows from the marriage condition. More generally, any regular bipartite graph has a perfect matching.[4]: 2 

More abstractly, let   be a group, and   be a finite index subgroup of  . Then the marriage theorem can be used to show that there is a set   such that   is a transversal for both the set of left cosets and right cosets of   in  .[5]

The marriage theorem is used in the usual proofs of the fact that an   Latin rectangle can always be extended to an   Latin rectangle when  , and so, ultimately to a Latin square.[6]

Logical equivalences

edit

This theorem is part of a collection of remarkably powerful theorems in combinatorics, all of which are related to each other in an informal sense in that it is more straightforward to prove one of these theorems from another of them than from first principles. These include:

In particular,[8][9] there are simple proofs of the implications Dilworth's theorem ⇔ Hall's theorem ⇔ König–Egerváry theorem ⇔ König's theorem.

Infinite families

edit

Marshall Hall Jr. variant

edit

By examining Philip Hall's original proof carefully, Marshall Hall Jr. (no relation to Philip Hall) was able to tweak the result in a way that permitted the proof to work for infinite  .[10] This variant extends Philip Hall's Marriage theorem.

Suppose that  , is a (possibly infinite) family of finite sets that need not be distinct, then   has a transversal if and only if   satisfies the marriage condition.

Marriage condition does not extend

edit

The following example, due to Marshall Hall Jr., shows that the marriage condition will not guarantee the existence of a transversal in an infinite family in which infinite sets are allowed.

Let   be the family,  ,   for  . The marriage condition holds for this infinite family, but no transversal can be constructed.[11]

Graph theoretic formulation of Marshall Hall's variant

edit

The graph theoretic formulation of Marshal Hall's extension of the marriage theorem can be stated as follows: Given a bipartite graph with sides A and B, we say that a subset C of B is smaller than or equal in size to a subset D of A in the graph if there exists an injection in the graph (namely, using only edges of the graph) from C to D, and that it is strictly smaller in the graph if in addition there is no injection in the graph in the other direction. Note that omitting in the graph yields the ordinary notion of comparing cardinalities. The infinite marriage theorem states that there exists an injection from A to B in the graph, if and only if there is no subset C of A such that N(C) is strictly smaller than C in the graph.[12]

The more general problem of selecting a (not necessarily distinct) element from each of a collection of non-empty sets (without restriction as to the number of sets or the size of the sets) is permitted in general only if the axiom of choice is accepted.

Fractional matching variant

edit

A fractional matching in a graph is an assignment of non-negative weights to each edge, such that the sum of weights adjacent to each vertex is at most 1. A fractional matching is X-perfect if the sum of weights adjacent to each vertex is exactly 1. The following are equivalent for a bipartite graph G = (X+Y, E):[13]

  • G admits an X-perfect matching.
  • G admits an X-perfect fractional matching. The implication follows directly from the fact that X-perfect matching is a special case of an X-perfect fractional matching, in which each weight is either 1 (if the edge is in the matching) or 0 (if it is not).
  • G satisfies Hall's marriage condition. The implication holds because, for each subset W of X, the sum of weights near vertices of W is |W|, so the edges adjacent to them are necessarily adjacent to at least |W| vertices of Y.

Quantitative variant

edit

When Hall's condition does not hold, the original theorem tells us only that a perfect matching does not exist, but does not tell what is the largest matching that does exist. To learn this information, we need the notion of deficiency of a graph. Given a bipartite graph G = (X+Y, E), the deficiency of G w.r.t. X is the maximum, over all subsets W of X, of the difference |W| - |NG(W)|. The larger is the deficiency, the farther is the graph from satisfying Hall's condition.

Using Hall's marriage theorem, it can be proved that, if the deficiency of a bipartite graph G is d, then G admits a matching of size at least |X|-d.

Generalizations

edit

Notes

edit
  1. ^ Hall 1986, pg. 51. An alternative form of the marriage theorem applies to finite families of sets that can be infinite. However, the situation of having an infinite number of sets while allowing infinite sets is not allowed.
  2. ^ Reichmeider 1984, p.90
  3. ^ Haxell, P. (2011). "On Forming Committees". The American Mathematical Monthly. 118 (9): 777–788. doi:10.4169/amer.math.monthly.118.09.777. ISSN 0002-9890. JSTOR 10.4169/amer.math.monthly.118.09.777. S2CID 27202372.
  4. ^ DeVos, Matt. "Graph Theory" (PDF). Simon Fraser University.
  5. ^ Button, Jack; Chiodo, Maurice; Zeron-Medina Laris, Mariano (2014). "Coset Intersection Graphs for Groups". The American Mathematical Monthly. 121 (10): 922–26. arXiv:1304.6111. doi:10.4169/amer.math.monthly.121.10.922. S2CID 16417209. For   a finite index subgroup of  , the existence of a left-right transversal is well known, sometimes presented as an application of Hall's marriage theorem.
  6. ^ Hall, Marshall (1945). "An existence theorem for latin squares". Bull. Amer. Math. Soc. 51 (6): 387–388. doi:10.1090/S0002-9904-1945-08361-X.
  7. ^ The naming of this theorem is inconsistent in the literature. There is the result concerning matchings in bipartite graphs and its interpretation as a covering of (0,1)-matrices. Hall (1986) and van Lint & Wilson (1992) refer to the matrix form as König's theorem, while Roberts & Tesman (2009) refer to this version as the Kőnig-Egerváry theorem. The bipartite graph version is called Kőnig's theorem by Cameron (1994) and Roberts & Tesman (2009).
  8. ^ Equivalence of seven major theorems in combinatorics
  9. ^ Reichmeider 1984
  10. ^ Hall 1986, pg. 51
  11. ^ Hall 1986, pg. 51
  12. ^ Aharoni, Ron (February 1984). "König's Duality Theorem for Infinite Bipartite Graphs". Journal of the London Mathematical Society. s2-29 (1): 1–12. doi:10.1112/jlms/s2-29.1.1. ISSN 0024-6107.
  13. ^ "co.combinatorics - Fractional Matching version of Hall's Marriage theorem". MathOverflow. Retrieved 2020-06-29.

References

edit
edit

This article incorporates material from proof of Hall's marriage theorem on PlanetMath, which is licensed under the Creative Commons Attribution/Share-Alike License.