In algebraic geometry, a proper morphism between schemes is an analog of a proper map between complex analytic spaces.

Some authors call a proper variety over a field a complete variety. For example, every projective variety over a field is proper over . A scheme of finite type over the complex numbers (for example, a variety) is proper over C if and only if the space (C) of complex points with the classical (Euclidean) topology is compact and Hausdorff.

A closed immersion is proper. A morphism is finite if and only if it is proper and quasi-finite.

Definition

edit

A morphism   of schemes is called universally closed if for every scheme   with a morphism  , the projection from the fiber product

 

is a closed map of the underlying topological spaces. A morphism of schemes is called proper if it is separated, of finite type, and universally closed ([EGA] II, 5.4.1 [1]). One also says that   is proper over  . In particular, a variety   over a field   is said to be proper over   if the morphism   is proper.

Examples

edit

For any natural number n, projective space Pn over a commutative ring R is proper over R. Projective morphisms are proper, but not all proper morphisms are projective. For example, there is a smooth proper complex variety of dimension 3 which is not projective over C.[1] Affine varieties of positive dimension over a field k are never proper over k. More generally, a proper affine morphism of schemes must be finite.[2] For example, it is not hard to see that the affine line A1 over a field k is not proper over k, because the morphism A1 → Spec(k) is not universally closed. Indeed, the pulled-back morphism

 

(given by (x,y) ↦ y) is not closed, because the image of the closed subset xy = 1 in A1 × A1 = A2 is A1 − 0, which is not closed in A1.

Properties and characterizations of proper morphisms

edit

In the following, let f: XY be a morphism of schemes.

  • The composition of two proper morphisms is proper.
  • Any base change of a proper morphism f: XY is proper. That is, if g: Z → Y is any morphism of schemes, then the resulting morphism X ×Y ZZ is proper.
  • Properness is a local property on the base (in the Zariski topology). That is, if Y is covered by some open subschemes Yi and the restriction of f to all f−1(Yi) is proper, then so is f.
  • More strongly, properness is local on the base in the fpqc topology. For example, if X is a scheme over a field k and E is a field extension of k, then X is proper over k if and only if the base change XE is proper over E.[3]
  • Closed immersions are proper.
  • More generally, finite morphisms are proper. This is a consequence of the going up theorem.
  • By Deligne, a morphism of schemes is finite if and only if it is proper and quasi-finite.[4] This had been shown by Grothendieck if the morphism f: XY is locally of finite presentation, which follows from the other assumptions if Y is noetherian.[5]
  • For X proper over a scheme S, and Y separated over S, the image of any morphism XY over S is a closed subset of Y.[6] This is analogous to the theorem in topology that the image of a continuous map from a compact space to a Hausdorff space is a closed subset.
  • The Stein factorization theorem states that any proper morphism to a locally noetherian scheme can be factored as XZY, where XZ is proper, surjective, and has geometrically connected fibers, and ZY is finite.[7]
  • Chow's lemma says that proper morphisms are closely related to projective morphisms. One version is: if X is proper over a quasi-compact scheme Y and X has only finitely many irreducible components (which is automatic for Y noetherian), then there is a projective surjective morphism g: WX such that W is projective over Y. Moreover, one can arrange that g is an isomorphism over a dense open subset U of X, and that g−1(U) is dense in W. One can also arrange that W is integral if X is integral.[8]
  • Nagata's compactification theorem, as generalized by Deligne, says that a separated morphism of finite type between quasi-compact and quasi-separated schemes factors as an open immersion followed by a proper morphism.[9]
  • Proper morphisms between locally noetherian schemes preserve coherent sheaves, in the sense that the higher direct images Rif(F) (in particular the direct image f(F)) of a coherent sheaf F are coherent (EGA III, 3.2.1). (Analogously, for a proper map between complex analytic spaces, Grauert and Remmert showed that the higher direct images preserve coherent analytic sheaves.) As a very special case: the ring of regular functions on a proper scheme X over a field k has finite dimension as a k-vector space. By contrast, the ring of regular functions on the affine line over k is the polynomial ring k[x], which does not have finite dimension as a k-vector space.
  • There is also a slightly stronger statement of this:(EGA III, 3.2.4) let   be a morphism of finite type, S locally noetherian and   a  -module. If the support of F is proper over S, then for each   the higher direct image   is coherent.
  • For a scheme X of finite type over the complex numbers, the set X(C) of complex points is a complex analytic space, using the classical (Euclidean) topology. For X and Y separated and of finite type over C, a morphism f: XY over C is proper if and only if the continuous map f: X(C) → Y(C) is proper in the sense that the inverse image of every compact set is compact.[10]
  • If f: XY and g: YZ are such that gf is proper and g is separated, then f is proper. This can for example be easily proven using the following criterion.
 
Valuative criterion of properness

Valuative criterion of properness

edit

There is a very intuitive criterion for properness which goes back to Chevalley. It is commonly called the valuative criterion of properness. Let f: XY be a morphism of finite type of noetherian schemes. Then f is proper if and only if for all discrete valuation rings R with fraction field K and for any K-valued point xX(K) that maps to a point f(x) that is defined over R, there is a unique lift of x to  . (EGA II, 7.3.8). More generally, a quasi-separated morphism f: XY of finite type (note: finite type includes quasi-compact) of 'any' schemes X, Y is proper if and only if for all valuation rings R with fraction field K and for any K-valued point xX(K) that maps to a point f(x) that is defined over R, there is a unique lift of x to  . (Stacks project Tags 01KF and 01KY). Noting that Spec K is the generic point of Spec R and discrete valuation rings are precisely the regular local one-dimensional rings, one may rephrase the criterion: given a regular curve on Y (corresponding to the morphism s: Spec RY) and given a lift of the generic point of this curve to X, f is proper if and only if there is exactly one way to complete the curve.

Similarly, f is separated if and only if in every such diagram, there is at most one lift  .

For example, given the valuative criterion, it becomes easy to check that projective space Pn is proper over a field (or even over Z). One simply observes that for a discrete valuation ring R with fraction field K, every K-point [x0,...,xn] of projective space comes from an R-point, by scaling the coordinates so that all lie in R and at least one is a unit in R.

Geometric interpretation with disks

edit

One of the motivating examples for the valuative criterion of properness is the interpretation of   as an infinitesimal disk, or complex-analytically, as the disk  . This comes from the fact that every power series

 

converges in some disk of radius   around the origin. Then, using a change of coordinates, this can be expressed as a power series on the unit disk. Then, if we invert  , this is the ring   which are the power series which may have a pole at the origin. This is represented topologically as the open disk   with the origin removed. For a morphism of schemes over  , this is given by the commutative diagram

 

Then, the valuative criterion for properness would be a filling in of the point   in the image of  .

Example

edit

It's instructive to look at a counter-example to see why the valuative criterion of properness should hold on spaces analogous to closed compact manifolds. If we take   and  , then a morphism   factors through an affine chart of  , reducing the diagram to

 

where   is the chart centered around   on  . This gives the commutative diagram of commutative algebras

 

Then, a lifting of the diagram of schemes,  , would imply there is a morphism   sending   from the commutative diagram of algebras. This, of course, cannot happen. Therefore   is not proper over  .

Geometric interpretation with curves

edit

There is another similar example of the valuative criterion of properness which captures some of the intuition for why this theorem should hold. Consider a curve   and the complement of a point  . Then the valuative criterion for properness would read as a diagram

 

with a lifting of  . Geometrically this means every curve in the scheme   can be completed to a compact curve. This bit of intuition aligns with what the scheme-theoretic interpretation of a morphism of topological spaces with compact fibers, that a sequence in one of the fibers must converge. Because this geometric situation is a problem locally, the diagram is replaced by looking at the local ring  , which is a DVR, and its fraction field  . Then, the lifting problem then gives the commutative diagram

 

where the scheme   represents a local disk around   with the closed point   removed.

Proper morphism of formal schemes

edit

Let   be a morphism between locally noetherian formal schemes. We say f is proper or   is proper over   if (i) f is an adic morphism (i.e., maps the ideal of definition to the ideal of definition) and (ii) the induced map   is proper, where   and K is the ideal of definition of  .(EGA III, 3.4.1) The definition is independent of the choice of K.

For example, if g: YZ is a proper morphism of locally noetherian schemes, Z0 is a closed subset of Z, and Y0 is a closed subset of Y such that g(Y0) ⊂ Z0, then the morphism   on formal completions is a proper morphism of formal schemes.

Grothendieck proved the coherence theorem in this setting. Namely, let   be a proper morphism of locally noetherian formal schemes. If F is a coherent sheaf on  , then the higher direct images   are coherent.[11]

See also

edit

References

edit
  1. ^ Hartshorne (1977), Appendix B, Example 3.4.1.
  2. ^ Liu (2002), Lemma 3.3.17.
  3. ^ Stacks Project, Tag 02YJ.
  4. ^ Grothendieck, EGA IV, Part 4, Corollaire 18.12.4; Stacks Project, Tag 02LQ.
  5. ^ Grothendieck, EGA IV, Part 3, Théorème 8.11.1.
  6. ^ Stacks Project, Tag 01W0.
  7. ^ Stacks Project, Tag 03GX.
  8. ^ Grothendieck, EGA II, Corollaire 5.6.2.
  9. ^ Conrad (2007), Theorem 4.1.
  10. ^ SGA 1, XII Proposition 3.2.
  11. ^ Grothendieck, EGA III, Part 1, Théorème 3.4.2.
edit