In quantum mechanics, the consistent histories or simply "consistent quantum theory"[1] interpretation generalizes the complementarity aspect of the conventional Copenhagen interpretation. The approach is sometimes called decoherent histories[2] and in other work decoherent histories are more specialized.[1]

First proposed by Robert Griffiths in 1984,[3][4] this interpretation of quantum mechanics is based on a consistency criterion that then allows probabilities to be assigned to various alternative histories of a system such that the probabilities for each history obey the rules of classical probability while being consistent with the Schrödinger equation. In contrast to some interpretations of quantum mechanics, the framework does not include "wavefunction collapse" as a relevant description of any physical process, and emphasizes that measurement theory is not a fundamental ingredient of quantum mechanics. Consistent Histories allows predictions related to the state of the universe needed for quantum cosmology.[5]

Key assumptions

edit

The interpretation rests on three assumptions:

  1. states in Hilbert space describe physical objects,
  2. quantum predictions are not deterministic, and
  3. physical systems have no single unique description.

The third assumption generalizes complementarity and this assumption separates consistent histories from other quantum theory interpretations.[1]

Formalism

edit

Histories

edit

A homogeneous history   (here   labels different histories) is a sequence of Propositions   specified at different moments of time   (here   labels the times). We write this as:

 

and read it as "the proposition   is true at time   and then the proposition   is true at time   and then  ". The times   are strictly ordered and called the temporal support of the history.

Inhomogeneous histories are multiple-time propositions which cannot be represented by a homogeneous history. An example is the logical OR of two homogeneous histories:  .

These propositions can correspond to any set of questions that include all possibilities. Examples might be the three propositions meaning "the electron went through the left slit", "the electron went through the right slit" and "the electron didn't go through either slit". One of the aims of the approach is to show that classical questions such as, "where are my keys?" are consistent. In this case one might use a large number of propositions each one specifying the location of the keys in some small region of space.

Each single-time proposition   can be represented by a projection operator   acting on the system's Hilbert space (we use "hats" to denote operators). It is then useful to represent homogeneous histories by the time-ordered product of their single-time projection operators. This is the history projection operator (HPO) formalism developed by Christopher Isham and naturally encodes the logical structure of the history propositions.

Consistency

edit

An important construction in the consistent histories approach is the class operator for a homogeneous history:

 

The symbol   indicates that the factors in the product are ordered chronologically according to their values of  : the "past" operators with smaller values of   appear on the right side, and the "future" operators with greater values of   appear on the left side. This definition can be extended to inhomogeneous histories as well.

Central to the consistent histories is the notion of consistency. A set of histories   is consistent (or strongly consistent) if

 

for all  . Here   represents the initial density matrix, and the operators are expressed in the Heisenberg picture.

The set of histories is weakly consistent if

 

for all  .

Probabilities

edit

If a set of histories is consistent then probabilities can be assigned to them in a consistent way. We postulate that the probability of history   is simply

 

which obeys the axioms of probability if the histories   come from the same (strongly) consistent set.

As an example, this means the probability of "  OR  " equals the probability of " " plus the probability of " " minus the probability of "  AND  ", and so forth.

Interpretation

edit

The interpretation based on consistent histories is used in combination with the insights about quantum decoherence. Quantum decoherence implies that irreversible macroscopic phenomena (hence, all classical measurements) render histories automatically consistent, which allows one to recover classical reasoning and "common sense" when applied to the outcomes of these measurements. More precise analysis of decoherence allows (in principle) a quantitative calculation of the boundary between the classical domain and the quantum domain. According to Roland Omnès,[6]

[the] history approach, although it was initially independent of the Copenhagen approach, is in some sense a more elaborate version of it. It has, of course, the advantage of being more precise, of including classical physics, and of providing an explicit logical framework for indisputable proofs. But, when the Copenhagen interpretation is completed by the modern results about correspondence and decoherence, it essentially amounts to the same physics.

[... There are] three main differences:

1. The logical equivalence between an empirical datum, which is a macroscopic phenomenon, and the result of a measurement, which is a quantum property, becomes clearer in the new approach, whereas it remained mostly tacit and questionable in the Copenhagen formulation.

2. There are two apparently distinct notions of probability in the new approach. One is abstract and directed toward logic, whereas the other is empirical and expresses the randomness of measurements. We need to understand their relation and why they coincide with the empirical notion entering into the Copenhagen rules.

3. The main difference lies in the meaning of the reduction rule for 'wave packet collapse'. In the new approach, the rule is valid but no specific effect on the measured object can be held responsible for it. Decoherence in the measuring device is enough.

In order to obtain a complete theory, the formal rules above must be supplemented with a particular Hilbert space and rules that govern dynamics, for example a Hamiltonian.

In the opinion of others[7] this still does not make a complete theory as no predictions are possible about which set of consistent histories will actually occur. In other words, the rules of consistent histories, the Hilbert space, and the Hamiltonian must be supplemented by a set selection rule. However, Robert B. Griffiths holds the opinion that asking the question of which set of histories will "actually occur" is a misinterpretation of the theory;[8] histories are a tool for description of reality, not separate alternate realities.

Proponents of this consistent histories interpretation—such as Murray Gell-Mann, James Hartle, Roland Omnès and Robert B. Griffiths—argue that their interpretation clarifies the fundamental disadvantages of the old Copenhagen interpretation, and can be used as a complete interpretational framework for quantum mechanics.

In Quantum Philosophy,[9] Roland Omnès provides a less mathematical way of understanding this same formalism.

The consistent histories approach can be interpreted as a way of understanding which sets of classical questions can be consistently asked of a single quantum system, and which sets of questions are fundamentally inconsistent, and thus meaningless when asked together. It thus becomes possible to demonstrate formally why it is that the questions which Einstein, Podolsky and Rosen assumed could be asked together, of a single quantum system, simply cannot be asked together. On the other hand, it also becomes possible to demonstrate that classical, logical reasoning often does apply, even to quantum experiments – but we can now be mathematically exact about the limits of classical logic.

See also

edit

References

edit
  1. ^ a b c Hohenberg, P. C. (2010-10-05). "Colloquium : An introduction to consistent quantum theory". Reviews of Modern Physics. 82 (4): 2835–2844. arXiv:0909.2359. doi:10.1103/RevModPhys.82.2835. ISSN 0034-6861.
  2. ^ Griffiths, Robert B. "The Consistent Histories Approach to Quantum Mechanics". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Stanford University. Retrieved 2016-10-22.
  3. ^ Griffiths, Robert B. (1984). "Consistent histories and the interpretation of quantum mechanics". Journal of Statistical Physics. 36 (1–2). Springer Science and Business Media LLC: 219–272. Bibcode:1984JSP....36..219G. doi:10.1007/bf01015734. ISSN 0022-4715. S2CID 119871795.
  4. ^ Griffiths, Robert B. (2003). Consistent quantum theory (First published in paperback ed.). Cambridge: Cambridge Univ. Press. ISBN 978-0-521-53929-6.
  5. ^ Dowker, Fay; Kent, Adrian (1995-10-23). "Properties of Consistent Histories". Physical Review Letters. 75 (17): 3038–3041. arXiv:gr-qc/9409037. Bibcode:1995PhRvL..75.3038D. doi:10.1103/physrevlett.75.3038. ISSN 0031-9007. PMID 10059479. S2CID 17359542.
  6. ^ Omnès, Roland (1999). Understanding Quantum Mechanics. Princeton University Press. pp. 179, 257. ISBN 978-0-691-00435-8. LCCN 98042442.
  7. ^ Kent, Adrian; McElwaine, Jim (1997-03-01). "Quantum prediction algorithms". Physical Review A. 55 (3): 1703–1720. arXiv:gr-qc/9610028. Bibcode:1997PhRvA..55.1703K. doi:10.1103/physreva.55.1703. ISSN 1050-2947. S2CID 17821433.
  8. ^ Griffiths, R. B. (2003). Consistent Quantum Theory. Cambridge University Press.
  9. ^ R. Omnès, Quantum Philosophy, Princeton University Press, 1999. See part III, especially Chapter IX
edit