Donald Mackenzie MacKinnon FRSE FBA (1913–1994) was a Scottish philosopher and theologian.

Donald M. MacKinnon
Born
Donald Mackenzie MacKinnon

(1913-08-27)27 August 1913
Oban, Scotland
Died2 March 1994(1994-03-02) (aged 80)
Aberdeen, Scotland
Spouse
Lois Dryer
(m. 1939)
Academic background
Alma materNew College, Oxford
Academic work
Discipline
Sub-disciplinePhilosophical theology
School or traditionAnglo-Catholicism
Institutions
Doctoral studentsDavid F. Ford
Influenced

Life

edit

He was born in Oban on 27 August 1913, the son of Donald M. MacKinnon, Procurator Fiscal, and his wife, Grace Isabella Rhynd.[5]

He was educated at Cargilfield Preparatory School in Edinburgh then Winchester College in Hampshire. He then studied divinity at New College, Oxford, graduating MA in 1935. From 1940 he began tutoring at the University of Oxford becoming a lecturer in philosophy in 1945. In 1947 he became Regius Professor of Moral Philosophy in the University of Aberdeen, and in 1960 became the Norris–Hulse Professor of Divinity in the University of Cambridge. He retired from full-time academia in 1978.[6] MacKinnon delivered the Gifford Lectures in 1965 and 1966 on 'The Problem of Metaphysics'. A revised version of the lectures was published under the same name in 1974.[7]

He was President of the Aristotelian Society 1976/77 and President for the Society for the Study of Theology 1981/82. In 1984 he was elected a Fellow of the Royal Society of Edinburgh. His proposers were Thomas F. Torrance, J. MacIntosh, G, Donaldson, David Daiches, G. W. Anderson, Sir Thomas Broun Smith, Ronnie Selby Wright and G. P. Henderson.[5]

He was an Episcopalian.[8]

He died in Aberdeen on 2 March 1994.

Family

edit

In 1939 he married Lois Dryer.

Views

edit

MacKinnon is noted for his contributions to philosophical theology. He is particularly noted for the depth of analysis he applied to intractable theological problems, not least the refusal to simplify difficult questions in order to produce tidy or conclusive answers. His insistence on truth over tidiness is evident in his method of thought, an approach which some have labelled "open-textured".[9] The label derives from MacKinnon's use of literary, artistic, and political sources in his work – modes of enquiry which operate in contrast to the systematic and epistemologically narrow approach of some theology and philosophy.[10]

The intensity of MacKinnon's thought was matched by his lecturing style, which was marked by "his dangerously strong charisma, his ability to terrify adversaries".[11] Some former students admit to "spending more time mimicking him than following his arguments about Kant or Hegel."[12] At Aberdeen he was notorious among the students for talking to the ivy on the walls of King's College. [citation needed] Former students Dame Iris Murdoch, Philippa Foot, and Lord Williams of Oystermouth expressed deep indebtedness and admiration for his input into their intellectual development.[13] His influential input into important and relatively widely read thinkers' work, such as Williams and Murdoch, would suggest that MacKinnon's contribution to theology and philosophy is most strongly felt through the subsequent work of his students.[14] By contrast, MacKinnon did not publish extensively, and that which he did publish is largely in short essay form and out of print.

Realism and anti-realism

edit

MacKinnon often used a broadly Kantian metaphysics to determine the limits of a person's knowledge of God.[a] Subsequently, there is a close relationship between God and ethics in MacKinnon's work. But MacKinnon veers away from concluding that Kant collapsed God into ethics. Nor does he accept – the further conclusion that sometimes follows this – that Kant's epistemology precludes metaphysical realism, i.e. necessitates anti-realism, in ethics and theology.[b] In The Problem of Metaphysics (1974) MacKinnon develops a Kantian epistemology and comes close to an agnostic position on God, except for the proviso that ethical decision-making has the capacity to make agents aware of a kind of metaphysical realism. He goes on to argue that it is in keeping with a Kantian metaphysics to deduce God from this sense of awareness: "Kant [is] in the end a theist. ... His God does not enter into the texture of his exposition. ... he lies altogether beyond the frontiers of intelligible referential and descriptive statement. [But] we are all the time thrust outside those frontiers, precipitated beyond them by a moral experience on whose formal unity, in the most diverse human situations, Kant insists."[15] MacKinnon is, in this respect, against interpreters of Kant who consider his epistemology to have anti-realist conclusions. He is also quite specifically against the view that an anti-realist theology needs to be developed as renewed approach to Christian thought, e.g. the approach developed by Don Cupitt.[16]

Tragedy, construed as an ethical construct, plays an important part in the awareness of metaphysical realism. MacKinnon illustrates this with examples of tragedy from Shakespeare, Greek thought, and Jesus' parables, and concludes that "[i]t is as if we are constrained in pondering the extremities of human life to acknowledge the transcendent as the only alternative to the kind of trivialisation which would empty of significance the sorts of [tragic] experience with which we have been concerned".[17]

Selected works

edit
  • Christian Faith and Communist Faith (edited, 1953)
  • A Study in Ethical Theory (1957)
  • The Resurrection: A Dialogue (1966) with Geoffrey Lampe and William Purcell
  • 'Moral Objections' in Objections to Christian Belief (1967)
  • Borderlands of Theology and Other Essays (1968)
  • The Stripping of the Altars (1969)
  • The Problem of Metaphysics (1974)
  • Explorations in Theology, Volume 5 (1979)
  • Themes in Theology: The Three-Fold Cord (1987)
  • Philosophy and the Burden of Theological Honesty (2011)
  • Kenotic Ecclesiology: Select Writings of Donald M MacKinnon (2016)

Notes

edit
  1. ^ See MacKinnon 1974, passim, and MacKinnon 1987, part A.
  2. ^ See Cupitt 1984, pp. 136–140, for an example of these sort of deductions.

References

edit

Footnotes

edit
  1. ^ a b c d Bowyer 2019, p. 1.
  2. ^ https://www.thebritishacademy.ac.uk/documents/1469/11_07-Philippa_Foot.pdf [bare URL PDF]
  3. ^ Nussbaum, Martha C. (31 December 2001). "When She Was Good". The New Republic. Vol. 225, no. 27/28. New York. p. 29. ISSN 0028-6583. Retrieved 29 October 2020.
  4. ^ Bowyer 2019, p. 1; Shortt 2009, pp. 61, 63.
  5. ^ a b Royal Society of Edinburgh 2006, p. 597.
  6. ^ Cameron, Robin. "Donald MacKenzie MacKinnon" (PDF). Edinburgh: Royal Society of Edinburgh. Retrieved 31 October 2019.
  7. ^ http://www.giffordlectures.org/Browse.asp?PubID=TPPMET&Cover=TRUEGifford lectures page for Mackinnon, retrieved 6 December 2009 Archived 9 April 2010 at the Wayback Machine
  8. ^ Sutherland, Stewart R. (9 March 1994). "Obituary: Professor Donald MacKinnon". The Independent. London. Retrieved 31 October 2019.
  9. ^ Hardy 1997, p. 272.
  10. ^ Hardy 1997, p. 276.
  11. ^ Hobson 2005, p. 14.
  12. ^ Shortt 2009, p. 61.
  13. ^ Conradi 2002, p. 123; Foot 2009, p. 92; Shortt 2009, pp. 61, 63.
  14. ^ Kerr, Fergus (May 2004). Editorial. New Blackfriars.
  15. ^ MacKinnon 1974, p. 57.
  16. ^ MacKinnon 1974, pp. 43–44.
  17. ^ MacKinnon 1974, p. 145.

Bibliography

edit

Further reading

edit
edit
Academic offices
Preceded by Regius Professor of Moral Philosophy
1947–1960
Succeeded by
Preceded by Norris–Hulse Professor of Divinity
1960–1978
Succeeded by
Preceded by
Gifford Lecturer at the
University of Edinburgh

1965
Succeeded by
Professional and academic associations
Preceded by President of the Aristotelian Society
1976–1977
Succeeded by
Preceded by President of the
Society for the Study of Theology

1981–1982
Succeeded by