Wiki Education Foundation-supported course assignment

edit

  This article was the subject of a Wiki Education Foundation-supported course assignment, between 4 January 2021 and 14 April 2021. Further details are available on the course page. Student editor(s): Ainsmcf.

Above undated message substituted from Template:Dashboard.wikiedu.org assignment by PrimeBOT (talk) 00:28, 17 January 2022 (UTC)Reply

Propose move of this article

edit
The following discussion is an archived debate of the proposal. Please do not modify it. Subsequent comments should be made in a new section on the talk page. No further edits should be made to this section.

Consistent title (cf deductive reasoning and abductive reasoning) -- infinity0 23:22, 8 March 2006 (UTC)Reply

Special:Whatlinkshere/Induction (philosophy) - quite a lot of articles link to inductive reasoning already, which is a redirect to this current page. -- infinity0 23:37, 8 March 2006 (UTC)Reply

The result of the debate was move. —Nightstallion (?) 10:30, 13 March 2006 (UTC)Reply

The above discussion is preserved as an archive of the debate. Please do not modify it. Subsequent comments should be made in a new section on this talk page. No further edits should be made to this section.

Introduction

edit

First sentence should be "Induction is a form of reasoning that makes generalizations based on individual instances.[1]" The current introductory sentence is bloated and muddy. Anyone agree? —Preceding unsigned comment added by 128.138.64.101 (talk) 04:30, 8 September 2008 (UTC)Reply

I do. Although the point, that an induction is merely an educated guess, should remain. --Arno Matthias (talk) 12:10, 8 September 2008 (UTC)Reply
I do as well - the introduction, while sound philosophically, assumes too much of non-expert readership that expects something more accessible. The introduction needs to contain a sentence like this, THEN move to it's specialist engagement. The matter can be encapsulated in the lack of a definition of an 'inductive argument'. So the actual introduction, to someone without any training or expertise, becomes tautological between inductive reasoning and inductive argument.--Doingmorestuffonline (talk) 22:57, 9 May 2011 (UTC)Reply
Disagreed. The statement that "induction is a form of reasoning that makes generalizations based on individual instances" is not a claim that accurately describes all instances of inductive logic. The sentence makes an inaccurate generalization about induction, at least as far as I can see it, and is misleading in an intro paragraph. For example...
1)90% of humans are right-handed.
2)Joe is a human
Therefore, Joe is right-handed.
This is a very simple, and very common, usage of inductive reasoning that moves from the general to the particular.
Gilesbardsong (talk) 03:06, 24 October 2008 (UTC)Reply

Surely the 90% example is deductive.

90% of humans are right-handed. Joe is a human. Therefore, the probability that Joe is right-handed is 90%.

Is a completely accurate statement, since it is correct regardless of what hand he uses. Even if he turns out to be lefthanded, there was still a 90% chance of his being righthanded.

Bonsai Ent (talk) 13:03, 3 January 2012 (UTC)Reply

Your thinking is consistent with Keynes' usage, but one needs to acknowledge different concepts of 'probability'. Hopefully my recent edits make this clear. Djmarsay (talk) 15:15, 20 December 2023 (UTC)Reply

Discovery & justification

edit

There is a difference here between the role of induction in both discovery and justification. Can this be highlighted and explained, because a lot of confusion stems from this. Hume showed that we cannot learn from particulars anything beyond them. He also showed that no amount of particurs justifies a general statement.

jargon

edit

In the introduction of the article, the term "tokens" is used without explanation. Could the writer please explain it or use a simpler term? Peter Johnson 64.231.45.249 04:04, 5 April 2006 (UTC)Reply

abduction

edit

I find the sentence (in the section ==Validity==)

The writer John Barnes outlined a third method of reasoning, called "abduction", in his book Finity ...

highly questionable. --Arno Matthias 23:23, 24 November 2006 (UTC)Reply

And so it has been removed. Feel free to be a little bold the next time a random anon adds nonsense to an article. Simões (talk/contribs) 00:21, 25 November 2006 (UTC)Reply
...well... I haven't read "Finity"... maybe it is pure genius... --Arno Matthias 14:26, 25 November 2006 (UTC)Reply

To my knowledge, abduction was first introduced by the philosopher Charles Saunders Peirce. It is analogous to an "inference to the best explanation", but it is no inductive principle.

I never know what to do with the phrase "to my knowledge". Is this meant as "to the best of my knowledge", or "to my certain knowledge"? (The preceding post was left unsigned and undated. Edit history shows it to have been added 25 April 2007 by 87.79.208.178.) Milkunderwood (talk) 20:24, 5 January 2012 (UTC)Reply
I agree that this needs further clarification. Djmarsay (talk) 15:17, 20 December 2023 (UTC)Reply

References

edit

This article states many facts, of who said what, without proper citations, of where and when. Please help to improve. - 89.247.34.119 20:52, 19 February 2007 (UTC)Reply

Unclear explanation - "strong induction"

edit

The explanation for the following example of "strong induction" seems unclear:

"All observed crows are black. therefore All crows are black. This exemplifies the nature of induction: inducing the universal from the particular. However, the conclusion is not certain. Unless we can systematically verify the possibility of crows of another color, the statement may actually be false."

The problem is that the syntax of the final sentence--which I take to mean that we can legitimately conclude "all crows are black" from the fact that "all observed crows are black" ONLY if "we can systematically verify the [IMPOSSIBILITY] of crows of another color"--makes it difficult to untangle the logic of the resulting statement. If I follow the argument correctly, I believe the sentence should read: "Unless we can systematically verify the IMPOSSIBLITY of crows of another color, the statement may actually be false."

Califgrll 21:42, 24 February 2007 (UTC)Reply

Changed the relevant sentence, it now reads: "falsify the possibility" because I think its more precise than your (nevertheless correct) suggestion. This is due to falsificating the negation of a proposition being the only way to verify a proposition. -Dalailowmo 217.234.81.64 09:39, 25 May 2007 (UTC)Reply

There is also another problem with that section: "A strong induction is thus an argument in which the truth of the premises would make the truth of the conclusion probable, but not definite."

That's not true. Including more inductive cases has absolutely no bearing on the probability of truth or falsity of the statement. With the crows, for example, seeing MORE black crows doesn't mean it's any more probable that only black crows exist. This is actually an important point; it is the foundation of many anti-scientific claims. Famously, it is also the basis of Hume's system -- that we have no real evidence whatsoever to believe that the sun will rise tomorrow.

Furthermore, I think the entire section of strong vs. weak induction is pretty, well -- weak. Once you realize that additional cases don't have any bearing on the truth or falsity of a proposition, you'll see that they are, in reality, no different (unless you're one of the very few that foolishly defends probabilistic induction). -Tris

Correct me if I don't adequately understand this, however I think it would be helpful to have examples of "weak induction" that are not immediately recognized as false, in order to distinguish between "weak induction" and "inaccurate." Or at least some explanation of this distinction is in order. Earthswing (talk) 00:41, 16 March 2009 (UTC)Reply

Does my inclusion of Keynes' notion of 'probability' help? Djmarsay (talk) 15:20, 20 December 2023 (UTC)Reply

Citations

edit

I notice there are a whopping 34 citations for the last sentence in the introduction, and none anywhere else. Does this strike anyone else as odd? --Wayne Miller 15:01, 2 August 2007 (UTC)Reply

It's clearly an overkill, just a few of the most significant ones should be left. Reinistalk 23:19, 28 August 2007 (UTC)Reply

That's approximately the coolest thing I've seen on this site.

Article Lacks Clarity

edit

This article could use a general edit I think - though I am unqualified to do it. the following paragraph was particulary opaque to me:

It is however possible to derive a true statement using inductive reasoning if you know the conclusion. The only way to have an efficient argument by induction is for the known conclusion to be able to be true only if an unstated external conclusion is true, from which the initial conclusion was built and has certain criteria to be met in order to be true (separate from the stated conclusion). By substitution of one conclusion for the other, you can inductively find out what evidence you need in order for your induction to be true. For example, you have a window that opens only one way, but not the other. Assuming that you know that the only way for that to happen is that the hinges are faulty, inductively you can postulate that the only way for that window to be fixed would be to apply oil (whatever will fix the unstated conclusion). From there on you can successfully build your case. However, if your unstated conclusion is false, which can only be proven by deductive reasoning, then your whole argument by induction collapses. Thus ultimately, pure inductive reasoning does not exist.

Thanks! Cyclopsface 21:58, 27 August 2007 (UTC)Reply

The intro, especially the sentence with 34 citations, is currently an attack. It lacks a balance which John Awbrey's edits once provided, as this is only one type of reasoning cataloged by C. S. Peirce. --Ancheta Wis 10:14, 20 September 2007 (UTC)Reply

Inconsistent Treatment, Factual, and Technical Errors

edit

There are a number problems here, some debatable, some not.

There are two main types of induction. One is mathematical and produces certain results, and the other basically says (for example) that since the sun has not failed to rise every 24 hours or so, it will not fail to rise within the next 24 hours. In Principles of Mathematics (1903), Bertrand Russell calls mathematical induction "disguised deduction" and the other kind of induction he calls a method of making guesses. The first characterization is debatable, the second is not.

So the editorial claim, "Inductive reasoning is the complement of deductive reasoning." is at least imprecise.

Mathematical induction has been used when a set is constructed from an initial state and a generative principle, and it can be shown that all members of the set must have a particular property. Also proofs using mathematical induction use the natural numbers for the incremental and ordinal properties of the set, but mathematical induction is not a statement about the natural numbers per se (as stated in the entry on that subject).

The other kind of induction has been used when we project a trend. Neither mathematical induction nor the other kind of induction has anything to do with syllogisms or argument by authority. I haven't read the (what 5 with virtually the same title?) Popper articles, but I suspect some of the things being classed as induction are there because someone wants to declare that only deduction is logically valid and therefore lumps anything they consider not logical (i.e. the complement) into "induction".

Returning to syllogisms, deductive reasoning has syllogism as a result, but syllogism is not deductive reasoning per se (in the sense that Sherlock Holmes uses the phrase). Literal deduction consists in eliminating all impossible conclusions, leaving the set of possible conclusions.

Abductive reasoning is much closer to what is called statistical syllogism (though not as statistical syllogism is represented on this page). It consists of interpreting a large number of facts to infer a consistent general principle. Abduction usually appears in the context of diagnosis; so it is usually concerned with discerning causal principles.

Umberto Eco (possibly originally from Charles Peirce. Sorry, I don't recall the citation - probably Semiotics and the Philosophy of Language) described the three thus (I'm paraphrasing and augmenting):

Deduction proceeds from certain general qualities to certain logical cases to specific factual inferences. Induction proceeds from specific facts to categorical cases to inferring general principles. Abduction proceeds from specific facts to consistent general principles without inferring cases.

All this differentiation is subject to the same debate that Russell introduced (if he was the one who originally introduced it - I don't know), but it is almost certainly true that calling induction the complement of deduction is misleading and organizes the entries incorrectly.

Kikilamb 20:57, 11 October 2007 (UTC)Reply

Russell followed Keynes on induction. Djmarsay (talk) 15:29, 20 December 2023 (UTC)Reply

Regarding the section on Inductive strength, I thought Strength just meant how much new information the conclusion was telling you. For example (Weak)"Tomarrow the sun will rise." to (Strong)"Tomarrow , on the East Coast, the sun will rise at 6:51 am". The Weak Induction section refers to overgeneralization, which is topic in Inductive probability. I'm confused. —Preceding unsigned comment added by 69.124.128.196 (talk) 14:36, 2 February 2008 (UTC)Reply

Argument by Authority

edit

"Authority" in this context is a social status. There are many rationales for designating an authority, such as "Religious text X said so.", "My father said so, and my father wouldn't lie to me.", or the given rationale "The source has been truthful in the past."

It is one thing for us to say that a source has been truthful in the past and therefore they will probably be truthful in the future, and it is another to say that a source has been truthful in the past and therefore they are probably being truthful now. The latter is not a type of reasoning; in fact, it is an abdication of reasoning. On that basis, all designators of authority/oraclehood in this context, including ones that seem inductive, I call rationalizations rather than reasons. Since this is not reasoning, it cannot be some subtype of reasoning; and specifically, it is not inductive reasoning.

On that basis I have deleted the subentry. —Preceding unsigned comment added by Kikilamb (talkcontribs) 21:26, 13 March 2008 (UTC)Reply

Deductive reasoning vs experimental evidence

edit

Under "Validity" "By substitution of one conclusion for the other, you can inductively find out what evidence you need in order for your induction to be true. For example, you have a window that opens only one way, but not the other. Assuming that you know that the only way for that to happen is that the hinges are faulty, inductively you can postulate that the only way for that window to be fixed would be to apply oil (whatever will fix the unstated conclusion). From there on you can successfully build your case. However, if your unstated conclusion is false, which can only be proven by deductive reasoning, then your whole argument by induction collapses." - I assume it's possible that the falseness of the unstated conclusion could also be determined thru experimental evidence (direct sensual knowing), or is evidence considered part of deductive reasoning? You try oiling the hinge but the window still isn't fixed, obviously (before formal reasoning can take place) oiling didn't fix the window, or, inductively, an alternate hypothesis as to what will fix the window is generated - "hitting the window hinge with a hammer will fix this". --69.243.168.118 (talk) 03:38, 23 March 2008 (UTC)Reply

?"truth of the universal"?

edit

re:

Sextus Empiricus questioned how the truth of the universal can be established by examining some of the particulars. Examining all the particulars is difficult as they are infinite in number.

Can anybody explain what is meant by the term "the universal" in the above sentence? As the term is usually used a universal is not something which could be either true or false. The definition of universal provided at universals seems fair enough:-

In metaphysics, a universal is a what particular things have in common, namely characteristics or qualities. In other words, universals are repeatable or recurrent entities that can be instantiated or exemplified by many particular things.

On that definition a universal is not a truth-bearer/not the sort of thing that can be true or false. --Philogo 12:39, 29 July 2008 (UTC)

Sextus Empiricus is referring to things that are univerally true (true in all cases) rather than things that are only true in particular cases (under some circumstances, such as those one has observed). --Llewdor (talk) 20:13, 12 August 2008 (UTC)Reply

Science does not require induction

edit

The article asserts, "Scientists still rely on induction nevertheless." This is patently false. Science involves certainty with regard to disproving hypotheses (this using deduction), and then responds with new hypotheses (supposition). Never is induction used to form unsupported conclusions.

Applied science (engineering) relies on induction because it needs to act as if it knows what things are true, but scientists only ever know what things are false, and thus induction plays no role whatever in their work.

The claim that science relies on induction could be used to define unscientific claims as science. --Llewdor (talk) 20:19, 12 August 2008 (UTC)Reply

How could it do that? It is defining science as a subset of inductive practice, not inductive practice as a subset of science. You are making this flawed inference: Some induction is done unscientifically. Therefore, all induction is unscientific.

That isn't right. Science uses induction and deduction. (Any postulated "Law of Nature" is an induction, for example.) Pjwerner (talk) 20:28, 24 October 2008 (UTC)Reply

That's nonsense, science does not use induction. Induction does not exist. (Not only) Science (but every valid inference humans ever make) is purely deductive. A Law of Nature is a Law of Nature, not an induction. It would be allegedly an induction to say that this Law of Nature is valid because of this evidence and that evidence, but it's not really induction, it's merely an invalid argument. Engineering does not rely on some allegedly existing induction either. Engineering exploits physical laws, it doesn't rely on any Induction in relation to them. Further, science involves no certainity at all. Claiming that science "involves certainty with regard to disproving hypotheses" is so-called naive falsificationism, and has most notably been criticized by Popper (despite paradoxically being a view misattributed to him quite often). --rtc (talk) 12:28, 25 October 2008 (UTC)Reply

If there is no such thing as induction, all talk of "Laws" would be meaningless. That clearly isn't the case. I don't want to get in a huge philosophical dispute here, because I understand your point. But your point is a controversial one, and as such, both sides should be aired. Pjwerner (talk) 12:35, 25 October 2008 (UTC)Reply

Talk of Laws is meaningful despite there being no such thing as induction. It can only appear otherwise to someone who believes in justificationism and so confuses truth and justification. An extensive list of sources with various views from the ongoing debate were removed some time ago.[1] --rtc (talk) 12:48, 25 October 2008 (UTC)Reply

On what grounds could someone posit a "law" other than inductive grounds? Besides, part of science's purpose is predicting events. Without induction, how is this possible? Maybe it would be best to leave it at this. Again, I don't want to get into a heated philosophical dispute. But it seems to me that it would be POV to say induction does not exist. Put the perspective up there and leave it at that. Pjwerner (talk) 17:13, 25 October 2008 (UTC)Reply

Even asking a question beginning with "On what grounds" is presupposing justificationism, and justificationism is false. The answer is, he could posit a law on no grounds at all (which does not mean the same as out of the blue), and there is nothing wrong with that. The question "How is it possible to predict events without induction?" is a strange one, because already Aristotle, the inventor of induction, held that prediction works by deduction from the laws, and noone seems to have disputed that. So even according to Aristotele, induction plays a role only when we obtain laws from observations we have made, not when we deduce predictions from these laws. The article doesn't say that induction does not exist (although it would be a true statement; but the neutrality principle says an encyclopedia article should not take sides on some controversial issue); it says that Popper and Miller have disputed its existence. --rtc (talk) 21:41, 25 October 2008 (UTC)Reply
Are you sure you have understood Popper and Miller correctly? You ascribed this statement to them in the article: "Scientists cannot rely on induction simply because it does not exist." This does not seem sensible. The scientists use a method which they label inductive, and that method must exist since they use it. Therefore, in the sense they define inductive reasoning, it exists. If Popper and Miller define inductive reasoning in a different way, and conclude that it does not exist, then what use is their definition, and why is it at all relevant to what scientists do? Of course inductive reasoning as they define it must then be invalid and unnecessary, as well as valid and necessary, as everything is true about non-existent objects. It's also unclear how they can include Bayesian reasoning in this, since it is a method that is used, and therefore must exist.
As an aside, any non-inductive way of positing laws seems quite nonsensical by the definition of inductive reasoning in the article: "it involves reaching conclusions about unobserved things on the basis of what has been observed". Since the future is not observed, any non-inductive way of positing laws must produce laws which make the same predictions of the future regardless of what observations have been made. Either this definition is not the one Popper and Miller had in mind (in which case explaining their definition would be useful), or this is just another way philosophers have found to debate dancing angels on a pin. Looks like the latter, as even Bayesian reasoning is included by Popper and Miller, and that's as rigorous as inductive reasoning gets. -- Coffee2theorems (talk) 13:50, 6 December 2008 (UTC)Reply
"The scientists use a method which they label inductive" That's not true. Both that scientists use a method, and that this method is to be called the inductive method is an invention of philosophers, not scientists, though I won't deny that some scientists have actually started to believe it. You can see that easily: Aristotele wrote about induction long before science even existed! Popper and Miller do not define inductive reasoning in a different way, they do not define it at all. Popper and Miller attack the claim that inductive reasoning exists, in any meaning of induction that cannot simply be reduced to deduction. Of course the essentialistic definition that induction is simply what scientists do terminates all arguments on the issue quickly, but to claim "it involves reaching conclusions about unobserved things on the basis of what has been observed" goes far beyond that. "Of course inductive reasoning as they define it must then be invalid and unnecessary, as well as valid and necessary, as everything is true about non-existent objects." No; just because there is no dog with seven legs doesn't mean that "dogs with seven legs have eight legs" is a true statement. Note I'm presupposing the correspondence theory of truth here. "It's also unclear how they can include Bayesian reasoning in this, since it is a method that is used, and therefore must exist." But is it inductive and does it do what inductivists claim it does?
"any non-inductive way of positing laws seems quite nonsensical by the definition of inductive reasoning in the article" That is exactly what Popper and Miller deny. "Since the future is not observed, any non-inductive way of positing laws must produce laws which make the same predictions of the future regardless of what observations have been made." But that's obviously not true. Let's asssume we have some dispute about the color of swans. You claim that all swans are black, and I claim that all swans are white. Now let's assume we make an observation and we agree that we have seen a black swan, and let's further assume that this is actually the case. By pure deduction we can then conclude that the statement "all swans are white" is false and we should not use it anymore for predictions such as that the next swan that we are going to observe will be white. So the non-inductive method of falsification is a counter-example to your claim that past experience must be irrelevant to the question which predictions laws "produced by" non-inductive methods make (rather we should say: laws that survive the application of such methods). How about reading the books of Popper and Miller? They actually go further than solipsism. Solipsism says that we know that we exist. Popper and Miller's position is skepticism, which says that we know nothing at all (for all epistemological meanings of "to know"). Popper and Miller have some very detailed criticism of Bayesianism. See Miller's book Critical Rationalism. --rtc (talk) 20:46, 17 January 2009 (UTC)Reply

There are some interesting points here. But surely all scientific methods fit within the characterisation of 'inductive reasoning' at the head of the article, so the question is not 'do scientists use induction' but 'what kind of induction do they use, and how do they think about it?' (As a chartered scientist I found the Keynes/Russell approach, particularly as developed by Turing and Good quite useful, but others differed.)--Djmarsay (talk) 15:43, 20 December 2023 (UTC)Reply

Refs need fixing

edit

The refs section of this article is terrible. It has tons of references about inductive probability, and little to nothing on anything else. I don't have the background to select good references on inductive reasoning, but I strongly feel we should cut all but a few important refs on inductive probability and add refs on inductive reasoning in general. 99.233.26.121 (talk) 13:27, 26 August 2008 (UTC)Reply

Odd and even example

edit

I'm no logician, but I can't help but notice that "odd + odd = even" is given as an example of inductive reasoning, but this can be mathematically proven. Mathematical proofs are deductive, so it would seem to me this example is flawed. 12.216.1.235 (talk) 05:50, 29 September 2008 (UTC)Reply

If the argument was that "one or more pairs of odd numbers added together make an even number therefore all pairs of numbers added together make an even number" then it would be an inductive argument, even if there were a deductive argument that proved the result. There may be cases in the history of math where a result was known by repeated instances and later proved by deduction, e.g. I think Pythagoras' theorem. I believe Goldbach's conjecture is "known" by induction and remains to be proven. Nevertheless this is a poor example of an inductive argument since (A) it proceeds from just one instance (b) there is a deductive proof for the result. The example therefore is bound to cause confusion. There are less confusion well-worn examples that can be given, e.g. "Repeated observations show that if a price of iron is heated then it expands, therefore iron expands when heated". The traditional example for frailty of induction is "The dog observed that whenever he woke up early in the dark and narked in the end the sun would rise; therefore, the dog concluded, barking makes the sun rise"

PS Whether mathematical arguments are purely logical or empirical is a hot topic: see Philosophy of Mathematics.--Philogo 12:40, 29 September 2008 (UTC)

New induction form?

edit

I don't want to introduce original research here, but maybe somebody knows some source to be pointed to here, or can explain how to categorize a thought I've had. It seems to me that one important form of inductive reasoning is what I am tempted to call a "defeasible argument;" perhaps also a "ceteris paribus argument." That is, premise set S supports conclusion C, so that, if nothing else is relevant, then C follows. But of course there might be some other facts defeating the argument or supporting a contrary conclusion more strongly, which is why this is an inductive and not a deductive form. This often occurs in ethics, when clashing values are at stake, but can also occur in other cases. For example:

experiment X suggests that light is made of particles, so it is made of particles (other data may suggest otherwise, of course)

euthanasia may reduce pain and suffering; this is good, so euthanasia should be allowed (other values may be defeated by this, however)

etc.--ScottForschler (talk) 21:50, 15 January 2009 (UTC)Reply

Keynes and Russell regard an inductive argument as showing that something is probable relative to the evidence. Does that help? Djmarsay (talk) 15:46, 20 December 2023 (UTC)Reply

{{Who?}}

edit

To my understanding all science is inductive, it is simply that the statements who’s validity derives by inductive reasoning come to be the a priori axioms of the particular science. Anyways, another thing: I added template {{Who?}} on section Validity on the phrase “some philosophers” because I’d really like to know who they are. Thanks.--Vanakaris (talk) 09:42, 14 March 2009 (UTC)Reply

Can you cite any sorces for your understanding that all science is inductive?--Philogo (talk) 13:00, 27 April 2009 (UTC)Reply
Keynes, Russell and Whitehead all argue that the findings of science are necessarily dependent on induction, but the application of science needn't be. So it depends on what you think counts as 'doing science'. Djmarsay (talk) 15:49, 20 December 2023 (UTC)Reply

No I can't. What I meant is that science_1=physics is inductive (i.e. "all bodies fall" but we only have seen some - not all), science_2=chemistry is inductive (i.e. "2 NaOH + H2SO4 → 2 H2O + Na2SO4" but we only have seen this NaOH sample reacting - not all), and I reasonably assume the same (inductive reasoning!) for science_3, science_4, etc :-)! Seriously now: you are right. It is more accurate to say that "to some extent science is inductive" instead of "all science is inductive".--Vanakaris (talk) 07:59, 16 May 2009 (UTC)Reply

The use of the word 'infer'

edit

I couldn't help but notice that *infer* is used in several places in the article. Isn't inference inherently DEductive, or is there a subtlety I'm missing? In the first para: "This ice is cold. ...to infer general propositions such as: All ice is cold."

I suggest replacing the word (by those more knowledgeable of logic than I) infer with something like 'reach'. "to reach general propositions"... 68.102.45.46 (talk) 16:15, 16 October 2009 (UTC) AnonReply

Inference is not necessarily deductive. "Inductive inference" is a phrase frequently used in popular accounts as well as the literature on Bayesian inference, prediction theory, AI, etc. Wikipedia has a page on it with a few references: Inductive inference. earwicker (talk) 19:21, 8 December 2009 (UTC)Reply

Strong Induction; Weak Induction

edit

This part of the article seems somewhat imprecise: It merely gives a (relatively) strong case of inductive inference, and a particularly weak one, without discussing the factors proposed to scale with the strength of induction. Also, the titles are particularly poorly conceived, since strong induction and weak induction have already been coined to defined deductive(ish) mathematical versions of proof. So I suggest:

Firstly a change of title in this section to Strength of Induction.

Secondly the introduction of the factors which are supposed to increase the strength of a particular inductive inference from (e.g.) observations of As which are X to the conclusion that all As are X, namely:

1.The number of observed cases of As which are X.

2.The variety of different situations in which As were observed to be X.

3.The general consistency with other beliefs held of the result that all As are X.

followed by a discussion of the motivations of each of these factors, including examples. I would do this myself but I'm not really qualified to, and don't really know how to edit. 163.1.167.195 (talk) 23:29, 17 February 2010 (UTC)Reply

P.S. The fact that the first sentence of the article is simply wrong is quite annoying: there are two types of inductive inference (in this sense) - one from a set of observations to a generalisation (as stated in the article), and one from a set of observations to a specifice prediction (e.g. from 'all swans I have seen are white' to 'the next swan I see will be white').

This article evidently needs a lot of clearing up - it is extremely poor quality for what is a crucial centrepiece of philosophical debate. Not that I mean to whinge unproductively... —Preceding unsigned comment added by 163.1.167.195 (talk) 22:09, 28 February 2010 (UTC)Reply

Scientific laws as examples of strong inductive reasoning.

edit

I think a much better example of strong inductive reasoning would be the scientific laws we have today. The example with the black crows barely seems like mediocre inductive reasoning to me. The laws of physics, they are examples of strong inductive reasoning. 85.165.92.9 (talk) 22:35, 12 August 2010 (UTC)Reply

WP:BOLD. Just remember that it isn't the laws that are examples of strong inductive reasoning but the process of deriving those laws.--Heyitspeter (talk) 06:21, 13 August 2010 (UTC)Reply

What about this example of strong inductive reasoning:

All observed electrons have a charge of −1.602176487(40)×10^ −19 C.
Therefore:
All electrons have a charge of −1.602176487(40)×10^−19 C.

This seems like much stronger inductive reasoning than the example with the black crows. 85.165.92.9 (talk) 09:45, 13 August 2010 (UTC)Reply

I have changed the black crow example to the electron charge example in the article. If anybody have a better example feel free to replace mine with it.85.165.92.9 (talk) 16:06, 13 August 2010 (UTC)Reply

Well it's a bit odd since it's not a scientific law. And we have technically measured electrons and come up with different charges (though perhaps on somewhat imprecise equipment). What about:
The equation, "the gravitational force between two objects equals the gravitational constant times the product of the masses divided by the distance between them squared," has allowed us to describe the rate of fall of all objects we have observed.
Therefore:
The gravitational force between two objects equals the gravitational constant times the product of the masses divided by the distance between them squared.
I like this one because it's Newtonian. It'd be nice to use an example of strong induction whose conclusions are 'known' to be false, as it would drive the point home that strong induction is still only induction.
The difficulty with using scientific laws as an example is that they usually don't even pretend to be empirical. When Newton states, F=ma, he's not claiming that force is an object in the world we can interact with.--Heyitspeter (talk) 17:19, 13 August 2010 (UTC)Reply

Sounds good. Especially if you mention that Einstein's theory of general relativity gives even more accurate predictions.85.165.92.9 (talk) 17:29, 13 August 2010 (UTC)Reply

Maybe I'll test it out. A little wordy though. Can you think of any other 'laws' that are more compact?--Heyitspeter (talk) 19:46, 13 August 2010 (UTC)Reply

Well, the whole section about strong and weak inductive reasoning is rather black and white. Rather there are different degrees of strength. Perhaps we could argue for Newton's theory of gravity as being derived from strong inductive reasoning, Einstein's theory of gravity as being derived from stronger inductive reasoning, and the possibility for a new quantum theory of gravity being derived from even stronger inductive reasoning. 85.165.92.9 (talk) 21:21, 13 August 2010 (UTC)Reply

Induction is a method to process observations. Science typically adds something else: theory building. Theories combine observations with logical reasoning. E.g., there are strong reasons to assume that alle electrons have the same weight (in quantum theory, they are even found fundamentally indistinguishable). The fact that both the electrostatic and the gravity force are reversely proportional to the square of the distance is not the result of precision measurements showing that these forces are proportional ro "r" to the power -2.0000000001, but to considerations of symmetry. The theory of relativity postulates that laws of nature should be invariant for certain transformations - for the logical reason that the frame of reference should not matter. The equivalence of inert and heavy mass is not just the result of the observation that the two differ by an amount lower than the measurement error, but to the logical (and brilliant!) perception that the two can't be different. Of course, such theories are verified by measurements, and hopefully confirmed, but they are not founded on observations, in the sense that they are constructed from observations. Rbakels (talk) 09:48, 2 November 2010 (UTC)Reply


I hope no one disagrees but I took the liberty of removing the post regarding there is a discrepancy between Newton and Einstein about the force of gravity relating to relativity. The sun is located about 500 light seconds from the earth and even though we see it at where it was located, we feel it's force from where it is currently located. There is no retardation of the effects of the force of gravity associated with the sun, therefore using the equation of gravity as an example of strong inductive reasoning is an error. Moonstroller-2 (talk) 06:10, 4 June 2012 (UTC)Reply

Swans

edit

I added the example of swans, supposedly the standard example of inductive reasoning. The examples given a number of lines below may be confusing because they relate to subjective observations - which is not the point here. In my perception, the first paragraph of a lemma should tell the reader what "induction" is - which is imho explained easier by an example than by a formal definition. Details should follow. Rbakels (talk) 09:33, 2 November 2010 (UTC)Reply

I split examples from definition. I think giving a fairly complete definition and then a clarifying example reads easier than sticking an example in the middle of trying to describe what it is. I still think the section reads a bit awkward, so feel free to continue to rearrange it. GManNickG (talk) 10:01, 2 November 2010 (UTC)Reply

Please clarify "outdated"

edit

At the bottom of the introduction it says "Though many dictionaries define inductive reasoning as reasoning that derives general principles from specific observations, this usage is outdated". Does this really mean "this usage is outdated" (i.e. at some point in the past this was a valid meaning of "inductive reasoning", but it no longer is), or does it mean "this is an incorrect usage which was more common in the past than it is now"? I think it means the latter, but it would be useful to clarify this. If the former, it really opens a can of worms because some of the references in the article are from previous centuries when perhaps the "outdated" meaning would have been intended. 95.149.106.210 (talk) 21:02, 30 July 2011 (UTC)Reply

Have you read the cited source for this i.e.

"Some dictionaries define “deduction” as reasoning from the general to specific and “induction” as reasoning from the specific to the general. While this usage is still sometimes found even in philosophical and mathematical contexts, for the most part, it is outdated. For example, according to the more modern definitions given above, the following argument, even though it reasons from the specific to general, is deductive, because the truth of the premises guarantees the truth of the conclusion:

The members of the Williams family are Susan, Nathan and Alexander. Susan wears glasses. Nathan wears glasses. Alexander wears glasses. Therefore, all members of the Williams family wear glasses.

Moreover, the following argument, even though it reasons from the general to specific, is inductive:

It has snowed in Massachusetts every December in recorded history. Therefore, it will snow in Massachusetts this coming December.

— Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Deductive and Inductive Arguments, Deductive and Inductive Arguments

— Philogos (talk) 22:47, 31 July 2011 (UTC)Reply

As Kusername has explained below, the "counterexamples" given by the Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy do not really work the way its author intended, and they fail to demonstrate why the usage in question is supposed to be outdated. Given that the Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy is the lone reference supporting the usage being outdated, and this reference itself admits that this "outdated" usage is common, I find it hard to justify in the Wikipedia article that the usage is indeed clearly outdated, without further qualification. In fact, to me personally it seems more likely that the usage is not outdated at all, and that the author of the Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy is simply confused about the matter. However, given that the Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy is a reference, rather than simply deleting the offending passage I have weakened it to show that there are dissenting opinions on the matter. Elanguescence (talk) 12:03, 23 February 2014 (UTC)Reply

False examples of deduction and induction in a citation.

edit

Directly above, the citation says, "Some dictionaries define deduction as reasoning from the general to specific, and induction as reasoning from the specific to the general. While this usage is still sometimes found even in philosophical and mathematical contexts, for the most part, it is outdated.

"For example, according to the more modern definitions [...], the following argument, even though it reasons from the specific to general, is deductive, because the truth of the premises guarantees the truth of the conclusion: The members of the Williams family are Susan, Nathan, and Alexander. Susan wears glasses; Nathan wears glasses; Alexander wears glasses. Therefore, all members of the Williams family wear glasses.

"Moreover, the following argument, even though it reasons from the general to specific, is inductive: It has snowed in Massachusetts every December in recorded history. Therefore, it will snow in Massachusetts this coming December".

Really, its having snowed in Massachusetts every December in recorded history is specific, not general. This example is induction because it reasons from the specific to, in fact, the general, but merely leaves the general law silent. The example really says, "It has snowed in Massachusetts every December in recorded history. [Thus it is a general law that it always snows in Massachusetts in December.] Therefore, it will snow in Massachusetts this coming December".

Without the silent general law—the induction—there is absent basis for the word therefore connecting past events to current prediction. So the second example is induction (specific to general), and then deduction (general to specific).

The first example is less blatantly confused. Yet if we observe these three individuals—Susan, Nathan, Alexander—there is no confirmation that these three individuals are the entire family. No specific observation or any practically attainable collection of specific observations, barring an ability to experience every specific event in all of reality, verifies the truth of falsity of this premise. So it's a general law defining members of the Williams family, defining all other individuals, besides these three, as "not members of the Williams family". And if this general law is true, we can deduce the truth or falsity of a conclusion—about the entire Williams family—via specific observations.

In this first example, the specific observations—whose truth or falsity is experienced in the observations themselves—is the second set of premises, namely whether each individual wears glasses. We then reference the general law—that the three individuals are the entire family—to deduce that all members of the family wear glasses. Without this general law limiting the domain of the Williams family, there would be no deduction, just induction, about the entire family upon the specific observations of these three individuals wearing glasses.

In sum, there is indeed more to the distinction between induction versus deduction than merely the direction of interference—either specific to general or general to specific—yet the direction itself yields the greater distinction. Induction is inference from specific observations to a presumed general law that merely appears likely to the observer. Deduction is application of a presumed general law whereby, if the general law is true, the truth of the conclusion is necessary.

I suspect some sentimental agenda—characteristically human even among scholars—to elevate one element as the truth and subjugate the other. Both deduction and induction have their proper applications, however. Merely, an induction ought to not be treated as a deduction, and a deduction ought to not be regarded as irrefutable. Neither induction nor deduction is foolproof, for a general law's infallibility is not verified by any specific observation. A general law's infallibility remains theoretical (conceived), not empirical (observed). In practice it is exceedingly difficult to wholly disentangle deduction from induction, as humans necessarily operate upon presumed general laws.

Yet the infallibility of a general law premising a deduction is ultimately an induction itself. Upon the general law that when one fails to detect one's motion, one is motionless, it was once deduced, viz-a-viz specific and unfailing observations, that the Sun revolves around the Earth. This deduction was not meaningless babble of the ignorant—and it had its usefulness to structure and maintain the socioeconomic hierarchy called feudalism—just illustrates the limitation of empiricism altogether. Neither induction nor deduction is foolproof.

Kusername (talk) 09:32, 7 August 2011 (UTC)Reply

Edit: The decemberexample is general, not particular. "For all x, if x is a day and occured in a past december, x was snowy" is, as far as I see, a correct formalization of the statement. — Preceding unsigned comment added by 194.239.25.159 (talk) 12:36, 19 November 2012 (UTC)Reply

Your rule is general, but it is not the rule that is implicitly used in the example - a day x in the coming December has not occurred in a past December, so there would be no way to use your rule to draw any conclusions about snow in coming Decembers.
The December example as given has two steps, first an inductive one and then a deductive. The example says: "It has snowed in Massachusetts every December in recorded history." That means, we have a record of specific past Decembers, and each of these specific Decembers happened to be snowy. From this record of specific observations we now inductively conclude the existence of a general rule: "It always snows in Massachusetts in December." Kusername put this rule into brackets, because the example does not state it explicitly, but nevertheless this rule is implicitly assumed to exist and it is used in the next step, which would not be possible otherwise: "Therefore, it will snow in Massachusetts this coming December." This second step is deductive, but it is based on a rule that we gained by induction, by going from the specific to the general. Thus the example first uses induction to go from the specific to the general, and then it uses deduction to go from the (inductively inferred) general to the specific.Elanguescence (talk) 12:18, 23 February 2014 (UTC)Reply

Inductive reasoning vs inductive arguments

edit

As someone who has never taken a course in logic, the first sentence is extremely unhelpful. To me it could as easily read, "Kraft brand Macaroni and Cheese is macaroni combined with cheese, sold under the Kraft brand name." Can anyone write an introductory sentence that doesn't seem so circular? A similar complaint was made on the discussion page for the Deductive Reasoning article, section 'Awful First Page'. Vikingurinn (talk) 09:03, 14 August 2011 (UTC)Reply

I agree, the article is not well-written. Specifically, I would like to request a less vague definition in the introduction. From what I've now read elsewhere, it seems to me that a more concise definition of the term "induction" might be something along the lines of: "a generalization that has never been shown to be false." For instance, "all observed swans are white, hence all swans are white". This was a valid inductive argument as long as the premise "all observed swans are white" held true. But the moment that someone discovered a black swan, the argument became invalid. Any objections to this definition? (If not, it's only a matter of sourcing it.) --Anders Feder (talk) 16:12, 18 August 2011 (UTC)Reply

Keynes, Russell etc take a different view. They also claim that any attempt to 'define' induction is necessarily circular. I think the article needs to cover all usages. I have tried to clarify things in my recent updates. Djmarsay (talk) 15:57, 20 December 2023 (UTC)Reply

Unclear examples

edit

Are all 3 of the following , taken from the article, examples of inductive reasoning "This is an example of inductive reasoning: 90% of humans are right-handed. Joe is a human. Therefore, the probability that Joe is right-handed is 90%. (See section on Statistical syllogism.) Probability is employed, for example, in the following argument: Every life form we know of depends on liquid water to exist. All life depends on liquid water to exist. However, induction is employed in the following argument: Every life form that everyone knows of depends on liquid water to exist. Therefore, all known life depends on liquid water to exist." — Preceding unsigned comment added by 184.12.9.34 (talk) 06:01, 22 February 2012 (UTC)Reply

Good example. Keynes and Russell would argue that the conclusion could be made a valid induction not only for all known life but for all life, but you would need to include a hypothesis (such as 'the uniformity of nature') that might rather beg the question. Thus rather than ask if the conclusion is valid one asks if the argument is, and it might be if you make its assumptions explicit, as they seek to do. Djmarsay (talk) 16:01, 20 December 2023 (UTC)Reply

the cited biases are not specific to induction

edit

A citation is needed because the cited biases are not specific to induction — Preceding unsigned comment added by Albertttt (talkcontribs) 11:20, 3 March 2012 (UTC)Reply

Inductive definition excludes induction but is deductive...round and round we go

edit

"Note that this definition of inductive reasoning excludes mathematical induction, which is considered to be a form of deductive reasoning."

Huh? More context or explanation is needed. 67.172.162.207 (talk) 22:10, 20 June 2012 (UTC)Reply

the phrase "mathematical induction" is a misnomer. it's not using inductive reasoning, but rather it's using deductive reasoning. it's just called mathematical induction. — Preceding unsigned comment added by 76.19.102.88 (talk) 00:37, 27 July 2012 (UTC)Reply

"Inductive vs. deductive reasoning"

edit

As already objected above, here, too the reference is not verifyable. The sentence, "Unlike deductive arguments, inductive reasoning allows for the possibility that the conclusion is false, even if all of the premises are true." could not be fathomed in the adduced "John Vickers. The Problem of Induction. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)".195.4.79.241 (talk) 14:25, 7 December 2012 (UTC)Reply

Does my reference to Keynes and Russell help? Djmarsay (talk) 16:03, 20 December 2023 (UTC)Reply

liquid life example

edit

Hi, I just wanted to say that as an animist I take great offence to the example, 100% of life forms are based on liquid water. Since in the animist, or traditional view of the world, many things are alive, including stars, rocks, and even computers. It is also the case that in other religions such as Christianity, Islam and whichever that have spiritual life forms such as God, Angels and the like.

So that example of "100% of life forms" really Only applies to materialist atheist world-view which is a tiny percentage of the population.

Perhaps there are some better examples that can be made? Or perhaps it can be made more specific 100% of known Biological life forms are based on h2o.

Elspru (talk) 14:24, 25 April 2013 (UTC) — Preceding unsigned comment added by Elspru (talkcontribs) 14:22, 25 April 2013 (UTC)Reply

Also the wikipedia page on life form, specifies many different kinds of life, including technological, and spiritual. So I've gone ahead and specified biological life forms, to maintain consistency. Elspru (talk) 14:34, 25 April 2013 (UTC)Reply

August 2013

edit

I am surprised the paragraph in the introduction about science and human knowledge coming entirely via induction didn't get removed in '09. This paragraph also seems to contradict other pages on wikipedia with overlapping subject matter (eg. the one on the history of the scientific method). However, there are other pages that support it without citation (eg. the criticism section of the page on falsifiability). I think this paragraph should be removed. It is false (or at the very least controversial); its appearance in the introduction is unnecessary and inappropriate, especially stated as a matter of fact. Actually, the whole introduction seems only vaguely concerned with defining and explaining inductive reasoning and more about defending its validity. It is false because it says (1) theories come from observations and (2) that makes them probably right. As for (1), there is no restriction on the source of theories. Theories are not equivalent to predictions. The curvature of space is not a prediction but an explanation from which predictions may be worked out. As for (2), science cannot demonstrate this. Observations (and science) can eliminate some or all relevant, contending theories. They cannot make theories probably right. If we test three theories on a prediction that they make, and find two which make the same prediction to both give the correct prediction (for different reasons, say newtonian vs einsteinian gravity predictions). They are not some how simultaneously both probably right - observations cannot speak to this. --Cauzality (talk) 22:05, 16 August 2013 (UTC)Reply

The section was in fact only added about a week ago. However, it is no longer in the article, so your wishes have been fulfilled. :-) Arc de Ciel (talk) 03:49, 18 August 2013 (UTC)Reply
I see, it seems similar to what they were discussing before I guess. But the paragraph I was complaining about is the third one, starting: "Even though inductive reasoning may initially appear weaker than deductive reasoning...". I still see it in the article.--Cauzality (talk) 01:57, 19 August 2013 (UTC)Reply
Let's take this one sentence at a time. What's wrong with the first sentence? "Even though inductive reasoning may initially appear weaker than deductive reasoning (because its reasoning is not deductively valid), in fact inductive reasoning is the basis for most of what we know." The bit before the comma seems uncontroversial. As for the second part, I would change the last word to "learn" to avoid a tricky debate about how to define knowledge. Logical Cowboy (talk) 02:23, 19 August 2013 (UTC)Reply
Interjection - oops, I'm sorry. You are correct that it's still in the article - I misread the page history for some reason. :-) I would agree with LC's suggested change in the previous comment. I am about to leave Wikipedia for a while ("wikibreak"), but I'm sure the other editors here will be able to answer your concerns. Arc de Ciel (talk) 02:41, 19 August 2013 (UTC)Reply
Nothing before the first comma really is an issue thanks to the words 'may' and 'appear', so it's a subjective statement. What remains of the first sentence really depends on the unsupported claim in the second sentence (namely, its first clause). The last (third) sentence depends on this same part of the second sentence as well, so it really all boils down to the clause in the second sentence, "Science... works from inductive reasoning". That is were it all goes wrong. This isn't just about inductive reasoning as logic considered in isolation, but as a philosophy of how science is done (which is why it is superfluous to the article, really). But it is also wrong (see, and). Now, I know this next part isn't a good argument as it is an appeal to authority, but...: Apparently many philosophers reject or ignore Popper, yet other people do not. Courts recently have used Popper's falsifiability as a litmus test for science.--Cauzality (talk) 16:50, 19 August 2013 (UTC)Reply
I take issue with this whole paragraph too, but sticking to the first sentence: "Even though inductive reasoning may initially appear weaker than deductive reasoning (because its reasoning is not deductively valid)" -- this is completely circular, it just says that induction is seems worse than deduction because it is not deduction. I think what it probably means to say is something like "because induction produces probabilistic (uncertain) answers whereas deduction gives definitive (certain) conclusions" Jrht2013 (talk) 09:33, 21 August 2013 (UTC)Reply
Just to add another brief point: the claim that we know the sun will rise tomorrow due to inductive reasoning: this presumably is referring to the Sunrise problem as a famous example of Laplace's "rule of succession" (which is an example of inductive reasoning). It could at least link to the appropriate wikipedia page. But also, from Sunrise problem: "The sunrise problem illustrates the difficulty of using probability theory when evaluating the plausibility of statements or beliefs." -- hardly supports the statement in the paragraph we are discussing. Jrht2013 (talk) 09:41, 21 August 2013 (UTC)Reply
I've had a go at re-phrasing it to sound less subjective whilst maintaining what I think was probably the intended meaning of the paragraph in question, and also keeping it brief and I think relatively to-the-point. I also thought it was a bit strange that the introduction doesn't mention Bayesianism at all even though that is (I think) the most obvious modern form of inductive reasoning.
Inductive reasoning is sometimes used as a model in both philosophy of science (to explain how scientific knowledge is obtained) and psychology (to explain how humans learn about their environments). For example, the 18th and 19th century mathematician Pierre-Simon Laplace used a form inductive reasoning to quantify the probability that the sun will rise tomorrow -- a question now known as the sunrise problem. In the 20th century, statisticians such as Harold Jeffreys argued that observed evidence raises or lowers the probability of a scientific hypothesis being true in accordance with Bayes' theorem (see here), a philosophical position known as Bayesianism. Similarly, Bayesianism (being a specific type of inductive reasoning) features in some modern theories of cognition (see here) and brain function.
Jrht2013 (talk) 10:48, 21 August 2013 (UTC)Reply
I would be happy with your version of the paragraph. --Cauzality (talk) 02:03, 22 August 2013 (UTC)Reply
Cauzality, so it seems your problem is not with the whole paragraph, but just with that one sentence about science. I agree that it is imprecise. Jrht2013, your proposed para seems fine to me. With that said, I would like to retain the first sentence of the old para, or your rewrite of it. Differences between induction and deduction is something that many readers of this article will want to learn about, so it is better to say something about that in the intro. Logical Cowboy (talk) 12:35, 21 August 2013 (UTC)Reply
Mostly, yes. The other two sentences are wrong too in my opinion since they are really about 'science' thought they instead say 'inductive reasoning' (IR). It's the second that says IR = science. If they said: most of what we know is based on science; our expectation of tomorrow's sunrise is based on science; and, IR is claimed to be how science works, that would be fine. But they say most of our knowledge and our expectation of future sunrises are based on IR. I just feel they would fall with the second sentence (ie. science = IR).
I agree with your appreciation of how other readers will approach the article in regard to comparisons with deductive reasoning. I think we might be at a decent level of agreement here. --Cauzality (talk) 02:03, 22 August 2013 (UTC)Reply

So... how can we change the paragraph to that of Jrht2013. Everytime I tried to change this page before it was reverted almost instantly (new to contributing to wikipedia)? Also, what about a new statement/paragraph comparing induction and deduction, as Logical Cowboy supported? I doubt I'm the best to do this. --Cauzality (talk) 12:52, 27 August 2013 (UTC)Reply

Mathematical Induction?

edit

Mathematical induction is treated as separate, but if maths is based on logic, mathematical induction should be an example of inductive reasoning, and should not (if this article is correct) produce certain conclusions.--Jack Upland (talk) 06:56, 4 August 2014 (UTC)Reply

After the invention and labeling of Mathematical induction, the discussion about how "deduction" and "induction" should best be understood went on. Today, mathematical induction is no longer categorized as induction, but for historical reasons kept its name. Just read the introduction to Mathematical induction. It says there "Although its namesake may suggest otherwise, mathematical induction should not be misconstrued as a form of inductive reasoning (also see Problem of induction). Mathematical induction is an inference rule used in proofs. In mathematics, proofs including those using mathematical induction are examples of deductive reasoning and inductive reasoning is excluded from proofs." --Arno Matthias (talk) 12:12, 4 August 2014 (UTC)Reply
Interesting aspects mentioned here. How about the use of finite enumerative induction such as proof by exhaustion in mathematical proofs? Unlike proof by exhaustion, mathematical induction is a form of a infinite (number of cases) complete induction. These aspects should be mentioned in article.--5.2.200.163 (talk) 16:03, 23 January 2018 (UTC)Reply

I edited the preamble. I hope that helps.--Djmarsay (talk) 16:36, 20 December 2023 (UTC)Reply

making instrumentalism relevant

edit

I invite comments on a proposed revision of Instrumentalism, incorporating the conflicting roles of Popper and Dewey in defining the movement and its dependence on induction, and showing current practice of those roles. See talk: Instrumentalism, entries 20 and 21.TBR-qed (talk) 19:32, 13 September 2014 (UTC)Reply

This Article Is Completely Enslaved to an Ancient Notion of Certainty

edit

Since the time of Plato, philosophers held that for a belief to qualify as Knowledge, it had to meet a standard of faultlessness they called "Certainty". This was done by philosophers as a means of pre-emptively silencing any and all would-be critics, by proving a means by which philosophers could impugn critics' intelligence. With the emergence of Modern-Era Science and its all-too-obvious success, Philosophy's too-narrow conception of Knowledge threatened to render Philosophy laughably irrelevant and solopsistic. John Locke endeavored to resolve this issue by first, dropping the term "Knowledge" in favor of the more flexible term "Understanding," and then boldly arguing the all such Understanding was based on sense experience and powers of the mind/induction. However, the world was not ready for Locke, and David Hume reversed all of Locke's progress by reinstating the sclerotic standard of certainty whose pedigree can be traced back to Parmenides. The failure to recognize this critique of Induction as the reneging on the 2,000 years of human progress that it is just shows how powerful the God of Absolute Certainty truly is. Trentamj (talk) 19:08, 1 April 2015 (UTC)TrentamjReply

Well, are you going to profess to know when one does NOT know? MaynardClark (talk) 02:39, 2 April 2015 (UTC)Reply

I fail to see how a fair reading of my above-made point regarding the relative limits of knowledge and understanding between Ancient and Modern Philosophy can be fairly interpreted by anyone as my somehow making a self-contradictory claim to unjustified confidence in my own beliefs. The conventional premise that one’s beliefs must be entirely certain in order to claim that they are items of knowledge is, I submit, a die-hard retrogressive one, inasmuch as it expresses the DNA of the Ancient Greeks' quasi-religious (read: absolutist) notion of Knowledge as Sophia. I apologize in advance if I misinterpreted your comment. Its brevity simply leaves too much room for a wide array of understandings. Trentamj (talk) 19:46, 2 April 2015 (UTC)TrentamjReply

Do the recent references to Russell, who has similar views to yours, adequately cover your concerns? Djmarsay (talk) 16:39, 20 December 2023 (UTC)Reply

Bad "Description" section

edit

It's "WTF?"-level bad. This section is basically nonsensical. It uses a fake example, with a made-up 90% figure that came out of nowhere and isn't applicable, then tries to apply it to reality with a "we could have used this statement" hypothetical, then extrapolates from this that the "all" version is functionally equivalent to the "90%" version. It's frankly shameful and embarrassing that a WP article on a basic concept in logic is farcically illogical. Here's a directly analogous rewrite showing how dead-wrong this section is: "We could say that '73.5% of all cats are not neon green, thus any new cat breed probably will not be neon green.' We could have applied this to each newly discovered or developed cat breed, and since none of them turned out to be neon green, this means we can extrapolate from this reasoning to 'No cats are neon green, thus any forthcoming breeds will probably not be neon green'." The real-world conclusion does not relate in any way to the fictional premise, and has nothing to do with whether the fictional premise could have been applicable to real-world data. I can also posit that there's a 90% chance that respondents to this post will not be alien space gods, but that has F-all to do with whether and why "Since we have no evidence of alien space gods, odds are that the next poster will not be one" is valid inductive reasoning.  — SMcCandlish ¢ ≽ʌⱷ҅ʌ≼  21:38, 1 January 2016 (UTC)Reply

Stop moaning, start improving. --Arno Matthias (talk) 14:01, 2 January 2016 (UTC)Reply
The example seems a good one, but perhaps precluded as 'original research'. Unless anyone has an acceptable source for a similar example?
Russell regarded the conclusions of inductive arguments as only valid if suitably caveated. This example brings out the need for one. Seek a source! Djmarsay (talk) 16:43, 20 December 2023 (UTC)Reply

Fuzzy logic

edit

Every swan I have ever seen was white therefore I expect that all swans are white is an example of fuzzy logic not inductive reasoning. Inductive reasoning tells you whether something is a reasonable possibility or not. It is based on cause and effect. The example of what killed the dinosaurs is a perfect example of inductive reasoning. Just granpa (talk) 11:28, 9 March 2016 (UTC)Reply

See the characterisation of 'inductive reasoning' in the preamble. Maybe we need a section on fuzzy logic? Djmarsay (talk) 16:44, 20 December 2023 (UTC)Reply

This article is full of weasel words that induction produces nothing more than logical fallacies.

edit
Please see WP:FORUM. Talk page comments should be directly relevant to improving the article.
The following discussion has been closed. Please do not modify it.

It seems like we've got a whole bunch of people here that need to go and actually do some coursework on methods, then to stop by and realise like Guba and Lincoln implored the rest of the scientific community in the 1970s roughly 50 years ago now that not all problems in life can be or should be solved with objectivity when there is so much subjectivity in life and the objectivists are missing out on the rainbow. Personal anecdote: Meeting a psychologist whose mind exploded when they were told about neuroplasticity the first time because it didn't fit in their black and white box that the brain in certain circumstances can actually regenerate itself. They soon developed a good case of chicken little syndrome and that was the end of that discussion in a matter of brevity.{

You're simply missing out and should then come back here with a refreshed view on the matter once you've actually been out there, been to school and studied methods as you should have done at some point in your post-graduate career and then you should come back with a refreshed and rationalised world view. The force of the objectivists is strong on this one. I would quite like to see an objectivist quantify their reasoning on life matters such as "how to prepare a three course meal for a wide range of people with differing opinions about Neoconservatism, Communism and Rastafarianism.' Of course that is nothing more than an absurdism but you get the point. Seriously we can't solve the entire worlds problems with scientific objectivism. Some people need to get a grip. It is none the less fun to sit back and watch the brains of objectivists fall out of their heads if you can't quantifiably measure a social experiment as per above. It's like your parents took away all your fun toys as kids and put you in an electroshock box with nothing other than trigonometry papers. Objectivists seriously have no chill sometimes.

Please take this as a light hearted dig rather than a serious attempt at bad faith and more so please see this as a reminder of what you're missing out on when you choose to give up life's subjectivism. --1.120.150.50 (talk) 02:23, 17 March 2016 (UTC)Reply

cause-and-effect

edit

What is the difference between "if A is true then that would cause B, C, and D to be true" and "if A is true then by the laws of cause-and-effect B, C, and D will necesarily be true"? If not by the laws of cause-and-effect then by what for Gods sake? Just granpa (talk) 21:57, 21 October 2016 (UTC)Reply

The former sentence avoids the terms "law" and "necessarily"; this was the motivation for me to restore it on 12 Oct. Following e.g. David Hume#Induction and causation, I think these terms shouldn't be used in the context of inductive reasoning. - Jochen Burghardt (talk) 23:02, 21 October 2016 (UTC)Reply
This usage seems okay technically, but potentially confusing. I would delete a lot of this stuff, but maybe it helps some? Djmarsay (talk) 16:52, 20 December 2023 (UTC)Reply
edit

Hello fellow Wikipedians,

I have just modified one external link on Inductive reasoning. Please take a moment to review my edit. If you have any questions, or need the bot to ignore the links, or the page altogether, please visit this simple FaQ for additional information. I made the following changes:

When you have finished reviewing my changes, you may follow the instructions on the template below to fix any issues with the URLs.

This message was posted before February 2018. After February 2018, "External links modified" talk page sections are no longer generated or monitored by InternetArchiveBot. No special action is required regarding these talk page notices, other than regular verification using the archive tool instructions below. Editors have permission to delete these "External links modified" talk page sections if they want to de-clutter talk pages, but see the RfC before doing mass systematic removals. This message is updated dynamically through the template {{source check}} (last update: 5 June 2024).

  • If you have discovered URLs which were erroneously considered dead by the bot, you can report them with this tool.
  • If you found an error with any archives or the URLs themselves, you can fix them with this tool.

Cheers.—InternetArchiveBot (Report bug) 15:40, 13 November 2017 (UTC)Reply

WP DEPENDS ON INDUCTION & DEDUCTION. THEIR MEANING SHOULD BE FIRM.

edit
The following discussion is closed. Please do not modify it. Subsequent comments should be made in a new section. A summary of the conclusions reached follows.
Not merged per unanimous consensus against merging. I am closing this because people are still !voting. Tol | talk | contribs 19:56, 7 June 2021 (UTC)Reply

This encyclopedia accepts the premise of enumerative induction that the more editors who agree on the content of an article, the more accurate and useful that content. Induction is practiced on every TALK page. Editors generalize from a few observations, and deduce concrete conclusions from their generalizations.

WP contains 4 repetitive and fragmentary articles on induction: [Inductive reasoning], [The problem of induction]; [New riddle of induction],[Inductivism]. I would like to rectify this chaotic situation by rewriting and merging these 4 articles, retaining only the reasoning title. I ask you—a participant in relevant TALK pages—to judge my rewrite/merge project: SHOULD I PROCEED? Below is the current proposed outline:

Definitions. Induction generalizes conceptually; deduction concludes empirically.

[David Hume], philosopher condemner.

[Pierre Duhem], physicist user.

[John Dewey], philosopher explainer.

[Bertrand Russell], philosopher condemner.

[Karl Popper], philosopher condemner.

Steven Sloman, psychologist explainer.

Lyle E. Bourne, Jr., psychologist user.

[Daniel Kahneman], psychologist user.

[Richard H. Thaler] economist user.

Please respond at [Inductive reasoning]: Talk.TBR-qed (talk) 15:55, 5 January 2020 (UTC)Reply

To clarify, he wants to merge Inductive reasoning, The problem of induction, New riddle of induction, and Inductivism. To merge articles you should follow the procedures at WP:MERGE. - Richard-of-Earth (talk) 09:25, 6 January 2020 (UTC)Reply
THANK YOU. I WOULD FOLLOW THE RULES.TBR-qed (talk) 15:32, 7 January 2020 (UTC)Reply
The same discussion text can be found at the talk pages Natural_kind, Generalization, Categorization, Classification, Instrumentalism, Instrumental_and_value_rationality, Fact–value_distinction, Situational_logic, Abductive_reasoning, Scientific_realism. It is not quite clear whether some of these are intended to be merge, too. I'd welcome a commont of TBR-qed on that. - Jochen Burghardt (talk) 12:16, 6 January 2020 (UTC)Reply
PROPOSED MERGE OF 4 CONSIDERED RELEVANT TO OTHER TOPICS.TBR-qed (talk) 15:32, 7 January 2020 (UTC)Reply
PLEASE SPECIFY WHERE YOU FIND STYLE INAPPROPRIATE.TBR-qed (talk) 15:32, 7 January 2020 (UTC)Reply
I do not intend to try to teach you how to write for Wikipedia in this venue, however, here are a few points that are not necessarily most important, just what I noticed and can articulate. You use the lead to introduce the subject with information not in the body of the article. The lead should summarize the article. See Wikipedia:Lead dos and don'ts You put evaluations and opinions in Wikipedia's voice. See Wikipedia:Neutral point of view#Explanation of the neutral point of view and Wikipedia:Neutral point of view/FAQ You seem prone to puffery, like you are selling the subject. See Wikipedia:Manual of Style/Words to watch#Puffery Richard-of-Earth (talk) 17:41, 7 January 2020 (UTC)Reply
I am not asking you to tutor me. I am asking for examples of errors you think I have committed, so that I can judge your judgments.TBR-qed (talk) 21:10, 9 January 2020 (UTC)Reply
  •   Comment: [moved from Talk:Instrumentalism#Induction & deduction to here, jb:] Criticism? - I wanted to include a section with criticism against instrumentalism, but saw the controversy in this article and decided to ask for guidance first. I'm a new WP editor and not an expert in the field. My intention was to include the critique by David Deutsch at the beginning of "The fabric of reality", where he argues that scientific theories stripped of their explanatory aspects would only be of limited use, and that instrumentalism is not how scientist work in practice. I understand that Deutsch's book is not an academic work of philosophy, but I think that the article would be more valuable if linked to current debates in modern science. - Alan Islas (talk) 05:26, 6 January 2020 (UTC)Reply
THE REVISION INTENDS TO ADDRESS CURRENT DEBATES, WITH CRITICISM OF INSTRUMENTALISM. TBR-qed (talk) 15:32, 7 January 2020 (UTC)Reply
Ooops, my fault. I put it back, into an own section: Talk:Instrumentalism#Criticism. Sorry for the confusion. - Jochen Burghardt (talk) 14:02, 8 January 2020 (UTC)Reply
  • Oppose: I agree with Richard-of-Earth that the 4 involved articles are sufficiently long and fine, so there is no need to merge them. Problem of induction discusses justification for inferring future expectations from past experience, New riddle of induction discusses deviating expectations based on identical experience, Inductive reasoning discusses approaches to formalization of such inferences, in mathematics and computer science (admittedly, it currently overlaps unnecessarily much with Problem of induction, while e.g. the sections on Bayesian and Solomonoff/Kolmogorov approaches should be extended). - I'm not sufficiently familar with the Inductivism article to judge it; possibly it could indeed be merged with Problem of induction? - As for Fact, Fiction, and Forecast, one third of this book ("Forecast") presents Goodman's New riddle of induction, while the article about the latter also presents the extensive philsophical dicussion caused by Goodman; so there is some intersection of both articles, but they don't handle identical issues. - I (presumably) agree with TBR-qed that the interconnections between all involved articles should be established; I suggest by own linking paragraphs, rather than just uncommented "See also" entries. - Jochen Burghardt (talk) 12:54, 6 January 2020 (UTC)Reply
THANKS. USEFUL OBSERVATIONS. TBR-qed (talk) 15:32, 7 January 2020 (UTC)Reply
CORRECT. BUT IT CAN BE. TBR-qed (talk) 15:32, 7 January 2020 (UTC)Reply
  • Comment: @TBR-qed: Please refrain from writing in all caps. As WP:SHOUTING notes, "CAPITAL LETTERS are considered shouting and are very rarely appropriate." Indentation is sufficient to differentiate your responses from the preceding text. Also, although it is of little relevance to the outcome of this discussion, TBR-qed's first paragraph in this section does not seem accurate to me. The claim that This encyclopedia accepts the premise of enumerative induction that the more editors who agree on the content of an article, the more accurate and useful that content isn't true; for example, a walled garden on Wikipedia can attract like-minded editors, and the accumulation of more such editors is not likely to make the content of the walled garden more accurate and useful. Accuracy and usefulness of content depends on factors such as those addressed by Wikipedia's policies and guidelines. Regarding the articles in question, some reorganization may be in order to differentiate the articles, to establish their interrelationship as Jochen Burghardt described above, and to reduce redundancy. But I agree with the opposition above that nobody has yet made a strong argument for merging all four articles into a single article. Biogeographist (talk) 15:19, 8 January 2020 (UTC)Reply
  • Opposed:My fuller response is on the talkpage of the "Inductivism" article. Here, I mainly address merely the inductivism article, which I don't see quite addressed here. That article is about the philosophy of scientific method termed inductivism, whose basis is enumerative induction and its nexus of assumptions, but implies far more. Disputing inductivism, as perhaps all philosophers of science do, is not disputing inductive reasoning and its merits in decisionmaking, a practicality that perhaps no serious philosopher has disputed. It is about whether scientists truly develop scientific theories, let alone metaphysically true scientific theories, by a scientific methodology classifiable as inductivism, whether Baconian inductivism, even with Mill's methods, or the positivist modifications by August Comte or by the logical empiricists. For what it's worth, I think that, strictly speaking, "Problem of induction" and "New riddle of induction" could be topics within "Enumerative induction", but that the differing origins, consequences, and applications make that merge unprofitable. — Occurring (talk) 14:21, 23 June 2020 (UTC)Reply
The discussion above is closed. Please do not modify it. Subsequent comments should be made on the appropriate discussion page. No further edits should be made to this discussion.

inductive reasoning in the context of serving life

edit

If serving life is our raison d'etre, then "western civilization's" observances of inductive reasoning almost completely miss the rather obvious truth that in order to ethically/logically progress toward least work/cost/harm strategies to serve life, we must eventually sculpt a working definition of inductive reasoning as absolutely crucial and fundamental to our progress toward any/all achievements, toward our true potential. That is, in the absence of full knowledge, we must hypothesize by estimating highest probabilities, and thereby blaze paths of progress in directions of preferred outcomes, and adjusting those directions when new data requires. So while only deductive reasoning allows for programming circuit boards for predictable/repeatable behaviors, only inductive reasonsing allows for humanity to blaze paths of discovery toward reaching its true potential and enjoying the spectacular benefits. Wikipedia may ned to further consider what may be humanity's true priorities in deciding what is appropriate/relevant content for its articles. Rtdrury (talk) 17:56, 15 April 2020 (UTC)Reply

@Rtdrury: So, you want to add a section about the use of inductive reasoning as a personal development skill? If you have a citation to a reliable source that is not a fringe theory perhaps it could be added. Otherwise it is not Wikipedia's place to right great wrongs beyond giving access to reliable encyclopedia knowledge. Richard-of-Earth (talk) 03:36, 16 April 2020 (UTC)Reply
i sympathize with this, but A Treatise on Probability makes some points that add some nuance to your 'we must hypothesize by estimating highest probabilities' that may seem relevant after Covid. But this article already seems much too convoluted without going in to that. Djmarsay (talk) 16:57, 20 December 2023 (UTC)Reply

Is Problem of induction obsolete?

edit

In the near future, I intend to revise the article Problem of induction. I am motivated by the 2005 article with that name by Sloman and Lagnado in the Cambridge Handbook of Thinking and Reasoning, edited by Holyoak and Morrison. That article, it seems to me, makes the WP article obsolete in 3 ways. It eliminates detailed history of induction, already present in this reasoning article. It distinguishes kinds of inductive methodologies more succinctly than this article. And it provides examples of current work on the topic, which are not elsewhere available. I ask editors interested in this topic to read Sloman and Lagnado and respond whether they share my judgment of obsolescence or not—on the talk page of the WP problem article. — Preceding unsigned comment added by TBR-qed (talkcontribs) 15:12, 3 May 2020 (UTC)Reply

Note that TBR-qed is requesting that editors respond at Talk:Problem of induction § Is this article obsolete? where the preceding comment is duplicated. Biogeographist (talk) 00:52, 4 May 2020 (UTC)Reply

Culpable Ignorance of Aristotle

edit

Not until my edit 1038200885 on 11 August 2021 did this article have any mention of the Posterior Analytics. The tractate of Aristotle was the first to describe the science of demonstration through inductive proof.

Therefore this article can be safely ignored, along with most modern so-called philosophy. For an introduction to the topic that is sound and coherent, try s:Posterior Analytics. And avoid the Bacon. Jaredscribe (talk) 07:02, 3 March 2022 (UTC)Reply

I had a quick look but made no sense of it. Maybe I have been corrupted by Russell et al. Is there a brief but accessible summary anywhere?
"Why does light pass through a lantern? Because that which consists of the smallest parts necessarily passes through the larger apertures. Thus light is produced because it passes through the lantern in this particular way, and it also has a final cause—namely to prevent us from stumbling." Djmarsay (talk) 17:05, 20 December 2023 (UTC)Reply

Edits of 19th Dec 2023

edit

I have attempted some edits that I hope clarify and are not controversial and do not unduly alter the general 'meaning' of the article. As a mathematician who has worked with scientists (and others) I hope I have not unduly mangled any of the more philosophical content. I would be happy to review my wording.

As it now stands, the example on coin tosses seems a bit weak and maybe distracting, so I would rather omit it. I have also scanned some of the above remarks and agree that such an important subject would merit a more thorough treatment, but then we are in danger of 'original work'.--Djmarsay (talk) 20:26, 19 December 2023 (UTC)Reply

Any article about induction that is 'forbidden' to mention and link to abstraction, even as a see-also alone, is incompetently gatekept

edit

Any article about induction that is 'forbidden' to mention and link to abstraction, even as a see-also link alone, is incompetently gatekept. The same is true of analogy and other see-also items that are already here. Please present here any competent counterarguments to this basic logic. If none can be adduced, then those links will be present as see-also alone (let alone competent incorporation into body text). Thanks. Quercus solaris (talk) 18:43, 26 March 2024 (UTC)Reply

Why should there be a link to "abstraction"? What is the relation of induction to it? In an earlier edit you just said "Abstraction is usually involved", which is pretty general. Can you be more specific? - Jochen Burghardt (talk) 18:50, 26 March 2024 (UTC)Reply
So the question that you're asking is, "how is 'any of various methods of reasoning in which broad generalizations or principles are derived from a body of observations' logically related to 'a process wherein general rules and concepts are derived from the usage and classification of specific examples'? First just making sure I understand what the question even is. Thanks. Quercus solaris (talk) 18:58, 26 March 2024 (UTC)Reply
Awaiting response; the question isn't hard to answer, unless one is trying to find some way to make the answer be "no connection" against all odds of sense or logic. Despite the fact that WP:BLUE indisputably covers putting abstraction in the see-also section (given the blueness of the green spans above), I'll cite a reference when I add it there anyway, just to dispose of this rather odd challenge. I'll do that next week, after giving due time here for any possible argument that might be adduced. If anyone can adduce one, it needs to be brought here; otherwise, citing the reference will duly satisfy WP:BRD at the "Cycle" aspect. Quercus solaris (talk) 01:21, 28 March 2024 (UTC)Reply
It's not ever an "odd challenge" to ask for a citation before material is added to an article—that's how collaborative editing often works, no matter how BLUE one may find the material in question. Remsense 01:35, 28 March 2024 (UTC)Reply
What made this instance odd is two aspects: (1) the degree to which it is like reverting if someone added "crabapple" to the see-also section of "apple", or an article on dogs that contained no mention or link of wolves anywhere (two topics that are indisputably somehow related in the real world but whose Wikipedia articles fail to mention or link each other at all due to inadequate development to date), and someone merely added wolf to see-also section, and it's reverted with very little explanation except "please discuss this before adding" and also "can you explain how they are related?" If that were the normal way of editing Wikipedia, WP:BOLD would not and could not even exist at all, and neither would see-also sections (at all); it is not the WP norm that an edit so basic as that cannot even be made without first asking permission or presenting an argument in favor of it at Talk. The argument in favor of it is too self-evident to require all that; the types of edits that require pre-clearance before they can be made at all are ones more in-depth than that. (2) Citations are usually not given for WP:BLUE see-also items; it is very unusual to see citations added to justify the existence (presence) of a see-also item. [In lieu of any better sentence transition here,] I'm not looking to be difficult about it, but the reason I belabored it here is that I dared not simply make the edit (with reference citation) without first saying anything here to defend it and then see it get reverted again with another inadequate explanation. Thus I made sure to painstakingly (belaboringly) explain here the plan to take the unusual step of citing a reference to justify the existence of a plainly WP:BLUE see-also link, and provide a week's notice for anyone to see if they can come up with a plausible argument for reverting it, before a reversion rather than after. This is to prevent edit warring, per spirit of WP:BRD. Predictably someone might complain that this reply is too long. That's a catch-22. Since my choices are either to belabor the explanation here or to get improperly reverted with inadequate explanation, I chose the former. Quercus solaris (talk) 04:40, 28 March 2024 (UTC)Reply
My question ist simply what you intend to write about abstraction in the article. Just "Abstraction is usually involved" is hardly of any use for the reader. By analogy, I wouldn't like to read "Wheels are usually involved" in the article automobile. - One possibility might be to wikilink just the first appropriate occurrence of "generalization", which is (if we believe the lead of that article) more specific than "abstraction". - Jochen Burghardt (talk) 10:41, 29 March 2024 (UTC)Reply
Thanks, you're quite right about optimal writing/phrasing, and the "wheels are involved" example is a good one. I agree. In the case of see-also links specifically, the idea is that there can be a rapid de-silo-ing, and tagging of possible future deforking of accidental/unintentional forks of some aspects of topic scope, when two articles should not be entirely isolated from each other (i.e., no mention nor link anywhere) because their semantic and ontologic scope overlaps way too much for that to be OK — and to accomplish that minimum-viable degree even without spending a time sink for rewriting. The idea is to get them connected at all, as a minimum first step, and further optimization can come later. I should have just done that to begin with in this instance — the only reason I didn't is that I try to integrate such links (i.e., "wikilinks that shouldn't *not* be anywhere in this article") into article text rather than see-also when feasible without pouring lots of time into it, for various good reasons. But my lesson in this instance is that if I can't do a more convincing job of the writing rapidly, then my workable options are either (1) to stick to see-also alone or (2) to downshift into something more thorough. Thanks, Quercus solaris (talk) 14:21, 29 March 2024 (UTC)Reply